Skip navigation
The Habeas Citebook: Prosecutorial Misconduct - Header

Journal of Const Law Effects of Death Penalty Law on Criminal Justice 2008

Download original document:
Brief thumbnail
This text is machine-read, and may contain errors. Check the original document to verify accuracy.
OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL? THE EFFECT OF
EIGHTH AMENDMENT DEATH PENALTY LAW AND ADVOCACY
ON CRIMINAL JUSTICE MORE BROADLY

Carol S. Steiker*
Jordan M. Steiker**
Why care about the American death penalty at all? It constitutes
only a tiny part of the criminal justice system. Fewer than 50 people
were executed and slightly over 100 people were sentenced to death
1
nationwide in 2007, while considerably over two million people remain incarcerated in the non-capital criminal justice system. The
death penalty does not even constitute a substantial part of our system for punishing homicide. In a country that has experienced between 15,000 and 20,000 homicides per year nationwide over the past
2
decade, the number of capital sentences and executions last year
looks particularly trivial. The relative paucity of death sentences and
executions does not disappear if we focus on the high-water marks for
death-sentencing and executions in the modern era, with highs for
3
death sentences in the 300s (per year, nationwide) and executions
4
hovering close to 100 (per year, nationwide).
By any metric, capital punishment receives a disproportionate
share of popular, political, and legal attention. The sheer number of
films, books, magazine, and newspaper articles discussing and depicting capital cases would suggest that capital prosecutions, sentences,

*
**
1

2
3

4

Howard J. and Katherine W. Aibel Professor of Law, Harvard Law School.
Judge Robert M. Parker Chair in Law, University of Texas School of Law.
Death
Penalty
Information
Center,
Executions
by
Year,
http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/executions-year (last visited Nov. 5, 2008) (specifying
42 executions in 2007); Death Penalty Information Center, Death Sentences by Year:
1977–2007, http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/death-sentences-year-1977-2007 (last visited Nov. 5, 2008) (specifying 110 death sentences in 2007).
U.S.
Department
of
Justice,
Bureau
of
Justice
Statistics,
http://www.ojp.usdoj.gov/bjs/homicide/hmrt.htm#counts (last visited Nov. 5, 2008).
Death Penalty Information Center, Death Sentences by Year:
1977–2007,
http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/death-sentences-year-1977-2007 (last visited Nov. 5,
2008) (showing a high of 326 death sentences in 1995).
Death
Penalty
Information
Center,
Executions
by
Year,
http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/executions-year (last visited Nov. 5, 2008) (showing a
high of 98 executions in 1999).

155

156

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

and executions are far more common than they actually are. On the
political side, state legislatures devote considerable attention to prevailing capital procedures and proposed reforms, despite, in relative
terms, the extraordinary infrequency of capital cases and the increasingly large share of state resources consumed by non-capital incarceration. At the federal level, Congress, which has virtually nothing
to say about state non-capital policies, has sought to influence state
postconviction procedures in capital cases by creating special rules in
federal habeas for states that adopt preferred postconviction stan5
dards for representation in capital cases. The complete absence of
any federal policy addressing the states’ unprecedented experiment
with mass incarceration stands in notable contrast to Congress’s attention to the ways in which federal review of capital cases can influence state capital policies.
On the legal side, observers have long noted the disproportionate
presence of capital cases in state and federal litigation of criminal issues. One reason the death penalty remains more expensive than
long-term incarceration (even incarceration for life) is the fact that
states give capital defendants—and only capital defendants—the
right at several different stages to challenge their convictions and sentences. Whereas non-capital inmates often are afforded only discretionary review to the highest state court on direct appeal, capital inmates have review as of right. Whereas indigent non-capital inmates
have no right to counsel in state postconviction and federal habeas
proceedings, and must therefore litigate pro se (if at all), indigent
death-sentenced inmates are generally provided counsel in both state
and federal postconviction litigation. As a result, criminal litigation
at the highest levels, even of non-capital issues, disproportionately occurs in capital cases. Moreover, the growth of distinctive doctrines
surrounding the administration of capital punishment (concerning
voir dire practices, the adequacy of state capital statutes, and proportionality limits on the imposition of the death penalty) has contributed to the disproportionate presence of capital cases on the docket
of the Supreme Court. Whereas capital defendants account for considerably less than one-tenth of one percent of criminal defendants
prosecuted for crime in any given year, capital cases have occupied
somewhere between one-quarter and one-half of the state criminal
cases within the Court’s docket over the past decade. Indeed, if one’s
exposure to the American criminal justice system were confined to

5

See 28 U.S.C. §§ 2261–2266 (2006).

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

157

attending arguments and reading opinions of the U.S. Supreme
Court, one might believe that capital prosecutions greatly outnumber
speeding violations, burglaries, or drug offenses.
Given the astronomical rise in our non-capital prison population
and the enormous social, political, and economic consequences of
such growth, what could explain or justify the extraordinary attention
directed toward our prevailing capital practices? One answer that
progressive reformers of the criminal justice system might offer is that
the drama and high political salience of capital punishment opens a
window to the entire criminal process and generates constitutional
doctrines and criminal justice policies that might never otherwise
come into being as a consequence of the much greater indifference
that courts, policy makers, and the general public display toward noncapital criminal proceedings. To bolster such a claim, such reformers
6
7
could point to cases like Norris v. Alabama or Strickland v. Washington,
in which the Supreme Court generated important constitutional
holdings for all criminal defendants in cases involving capital trials.
Or they could point to the reforms that were promoted and adopted
in the wake of dramatic death row exonerations, including DNA
preservation and testing, mandatory videotaping of confessions, and
higher evidentiary thresholds for the admission of jailhouse informant testimony. Such reforms have the potential to benefit noncapital criminal defendants, though it took the horror of the possibility of executing innocent persons to galvanize such reforms. The
death penalty, on this view, keeps criminal justice issues at the forefront of political and legal debate, and concerns about the fairness
and reliability of the death penalty might trickle down to the much
larger non-capital realm.
This is a comforting story, but there is a potentially darker story
here as well. The advocacy efforts and the procedural and substantive successes of the abolitionist movement may contribute to the
“walling off” or even affirmative disadvantaging of “ordinary” noncapital criminal defendants. In this Article, we focus on several ways
in which the salience of the death penalty in American criminal justice debates and litigation might entrench attitudes and practices
detrimental to the non-capital side of the docket.
In terms of advocacy, the focus on innocence in the capital context, though it has brought some salutary reforms, also tends to de6
7

294 U.S. 587 (1935) (holding that defendant was denied equal protection based on the
exclusion of persons of his race from the jury).
466 U.S. 668 (1984) (recognizing constitutional right to effective assistance of counsel).

158

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

flect focus from non-innocence related issues such as discrimination,
inadequate representation, and excessive punishment (even for those
guilty of the underlying offense). We believe that these issues are of
far greater significance and deserving of more attention than the issue of wrongful convictions in the capital context, though we recognize that concerns about executing the innocent have struck a chord
in popular sentiment and produced a wave of critical attention focused on the American death penalty. It is too early to tell whether
the innocence revolution will lead to the beginning of the end of the
American death penalty or stabilize the death penalty by prompting
the adoption of reforms intended to reduce the risk of executing innocents.
At the same time, an innocence focus on the non-capital side
seems like a less promising tradeoff for those concerned about the
prevailing pathologies within our non-capital system. Innocents are
undoubtedly included in the growing ranks of the incarcerated. But
the problems with mass incarceration as a social policy extend far beyond “wrongful convictions.” In particular, the sheer punitiveness of
our current non-capital system is unlikely to be challenged by a focus
on innocence. Many of the reforms generated by an innocence focus
tend to reinforce the basic “justice” of non-capital convictions and
sentences of the “guilty,” thereby deflecting more encompassing challenges to the status quo. In addition, trumpeting the vindication of
the innocent as the highest value within our criminal justice system
undermines the appropriate and traditional role of defense lawyers in
their representation of clients, including the guilty.
Another major policy focus on the abolitionist side has been to
support life-without-possibility-of-parole (“LWOP”) as a sentencing
alternative to the death penalty. The widespread adoption of this alternative has likely contributed substantially to the extraordinary decline in death sentencing nationwide—a greater than 50% decline
over the past decade. Here, too, reform of the death penalty has had
its costs for non-capital inmates. In order to prevent death sentences
and executions, abolitionists have championed LWOP as a workable
and humane alternative to the death penalty. Over the past decade,
the number of inmates sentenced to LWOP has climbed astronomically, and it may well be that the widespread adoption of LWOP,
achieved in part because of the alliance of the abolitionist left and
tough-on-crime right, has significantly increased the sentences of the
many in order to make less likely the already unlikely execution of
the few.

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

159

On the doctrinal side, some of the most significant limitations on
the implementation of the death penalty have been achieved only by
expressly relegating non-capital defendants to lesser protections. The
Court’s increasingly robust proportionality doctrine in capital cases
has been withheld from non-capital defendants, with the result that
there are virtually no judicially-imposed limits on the length of sentences for non-capital offenders, even for non-violent offenses. Similarly, the constitutional regulation of counsel has increased substantially in capital cases over the past decade, at least in the Supreme
Court, while the performance of counsel in non-capital cases remains
largely unregulated. In both of these areas, the additional protections for capital defendants may not have caused the Court to forego
greater protections for non-capital defendants, but the methodology
of treating capital cases differently has tended to both obscure and
normalize the pathologies that afflict non-capital criminal punishment.
In addition, perceived problems on the capital side have generated pro-prosecution reforms that have had severe adverse consequences for non-capital inmates. Legislative reform of federal habeas
corpus, for example, designed to reduce delays in capital litigation
and accelerate executions, resulted in significant and unprecedented
limitations on the availability of federal review of federal issues arising
out of state criminal cases. These limitations were applied broadly to
both capital and non-capital offenders. In this circumstance, the salience of the death penalty and the visible delays in capital litigation
were used to justify widespread restrictions on the ability of state noncapital inmates to challenge their convictions and sentences in federal court.
These varied examples suggest that the interests of capital defendants as a group and the interests of the much larger class of ordinary
criminal defendants may diverge much more frequently and substantially than their lawyers and (few) advocates acknowledge. Death
penalty “reforms” may undermine the prospects for reform of our
growing non-capital system. We do not offer a strategic account for
balancing the interests of non-capital and capital defendants. How
these conflicts should be addressed within the small community of activists and lawyers who work on capital and criminal justice issues and
cases remains a difficult and open question. The obvious starting
point, however, is to recognize that such conflicts exist.

160

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

I. ABOLITIONIST ADVOCACY: THE INNOCENCE REVOLUTION AND THE
EMERGENCE OF LIFE-WITHOUT-POSSIBILITY-OF-PAROLE AS AN
ALTERNATIVE TO DEATH
We are now in the second reformist moment of the modern
8
American death penalty. The animating concern for this era of reform is the danger of executing innocents. This focus differs considerably from the concerns of the earlier era, which focused more
broadly on the arbitrary and discriminatory implementation of the
death penalty as well as its unnecessary severity. In the account that
follows, we describe how the earlier period of reform linked the problems of the death penalty to the broader criminal justice system and
viewed abolition or reform of the death penalty as consistent with a
more encompassing critique of American criminal justice practices.
Today, the abolitionist or reformist focus on the horror of wrongful
convictions is largely distinctive to the death penalty and tends to obscure, and perhaps even entrench and legitimize, pathologies on the
non-capital side.
A. A Period of Convergence: Critiques of the Death Penalty Tied to Broader
Reform of American Criminal Justice
Although the United States is widely viewed as an outlier among
Western democratic countries both in its retention of the death penalty and in its punitive non-capital system, the United States was an
outlier in the other direction soon after its founding. The colonies
that formed our nation inherited the death penalty from England,
and throughout the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries the death
penalty was an accepted and unremarkable part of colonial criminal
9
justice. Soon after independence, though, Enlightenment ideals
10
prompted criminal justice reform. In several states, such reform included radically limiting the reach of the death penalty, even in cases

8

9

10

See Carol S. Steiker & Jordan M. Steiker, The Seduction of Innocence: The Attraction and Limitations of the Focus on Innocence in Capital Punishment Law and Advocacy, 95 J. CRIM. L &
CRIMINOLOGY 587, 589–96 (2005) (discussing the period of capital punishment reform in
the modern era).
RAYMOND PATERNOSTER, CAPITAL PUNISHMENT IN AMERICA 5 (1991) (indicating that “the
institution of capital punishment in the colonies was merely an extension of an English
legal tradition”).
WILLIAM J. BOWERS, EXECUTIONS IN AMERICA 3–6 (1974) (discussing the influence of the
work of Italian abolitionist Cesare Beccaria on Pennsylvania reformers, including Dr. Benjamin Rush, Benjamin Franklin, and Pennsylvania’s Attorney General William Bradford).

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL
11

161

of murder. The desire to cabin the death penalty was motivated in
part by an emerging belief in the redemptive potential of incarceration. It is no accident that the center of early death penalty reform in
the United States—Pennsylvania—was also the birthplace of the
American penitentiary. In 1794, Pennsylvania restricted the death
penalty to “first degree” murder and punished lesser offenses with
12
imprisonment. Within a few decades, Pennsylvania embarked on its
experiment with large-scale penitentiaries which promised to replace
corporal punishments (including the death penalty) with lengthy
solitary confinement.
By the mid-nineteenth century, several states had abolished the
death penalty (Michigan, 1846; Rhode Island, 1852; and Wisconsin,
1853), but most retained it. Few jurisdictions joined these abolitionist states during the latter half of the nineteenth century. Although
numerous jurisdictions abolished the death penalty toward the end of
13
the Progressive Era (nine states between 1911 and 1917), many re14
stored it in the wake of the First World War and the Red Scare. The
most significant change in capital practices concerned the rejection
of the mandatory death penalty; retentionist jurisdictions steadily
moved toward sentencer discretion in capital cases beginning in the
1830s, with the result that the mandatory death penalty was virtually
15
abolished nationwide by the 1960s.
From the Founding Generation until the 1960s, the American
death penalty was almost entirely a function of state law beyond the
reach of federal regulation. The federal Constitution supplied few
protections for state defendants beyond the general rights to due
process and equal protection, which the Supreme Court construed
quite narrowly; until the 1960s, the detailed list of procedural and
substantive guarantees contained in the Bill of Rights ran against only
federal authorities. Accordingly, the few capital claims that reached
the Court, including challenges to modes of execution (such as electrocution), were almost uniformly rejected. The notable exception
was the Court’s recognition in one of the “Scottsboro Boys” cases of
the right to state-appointed counsel in cases where the death penalty
16
is at issue.

11
12
13
14
15
16

Id. at 5 (discussing Pennsylvania, Virginia, and Ohio).
Id.
Id. at 6.
Id.
Id. at 7–9.
See Powell v. Alabama, 287 U.S. 45 (1932).

162

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

The death penalty as an American practice reached its height during the Depression, with a national average of more than 165 execu17
tions per year in the 1930s. Executions began to decline, though,
and by the first half of the 1960s, the nationwide average fell to 36
18
per year. One explanation for the decline in executions is the decline in the raw number of homicides; the number of homicides nationwide exceeded 10,000 per year throughout most of the 1930s, a
19
number that would not be reached again until the mid-1960s. But
the number of executions per homicide decreased steadily as well, with
a high of about 2 executions per 100 homicides during the peak period in the 1930s and a low of less than 0.5 executions per 100 homi20
cides during the first half of the 1960s.
The modern era of death penalty reform began in the 1960s with
a confluence of events. On the political side, the death penalty was a
natural target for the Civil Rights Movement given the unmistakable
racial aspects of its use. By the late 1950s, the Southern face of the
death penalty had become more pronounced as death sentences and
executions were increasingly confined to southern and border states.
The racial tilt of the death penalty was particularly evident in capital
rape prosecutions, as literally all of the 455 executions for rape after
1930 in the United States occurred in southern states, border states,
21
and the District of Columbia.
On the legal side, the Supreme Court began to reform states’
criminal justice systems generally and hinted at the reform of the
death penalty in particular. In a series of landmark decisions, the
Warren Court extended most of the protections of the Bill of Rights
to state criminal proceedings, including rights to counsel and trial by
jury, and rights against double jeopardy, compulsory selfincrimination, and unreasonable searches and seizures (as well as accompanying prophylactic exclusionary rules); most importantly for
capital punishment, in 1962 the Court incorporated and extended

17

18
19
20
21

WILLIAM J. BOWERS, LEGAL HOMICIDE: DEATH AS PUNISHMENT IN AMERICA, 1864–1982, at
25–26 (1984) (detailing executions, homicides, and execution rates by year for the
United States from 1930 to 1967).
Id.
Id.
Id.
Marvin E. Wolfgang, Racial Discrimination in the Death Sentence for Rape, in BOWERS, supra
note 10, at 109, 113.

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

163

against the states the Eighth Amendment prohibition against cruel
22
and unusual punishments.
With respect to the death penalty, in 1963 the Court signaled its
unprecedented willingness to subject capital punishment to constitutional constraint. Despite the near total absence of federal constitutional law regarding the death penalty, three Justices issued a dissent
from denial of certiorari on the question of whether the death pen23
alty is disproportionate for the crime of rape. Although the dissenting Justices did not mention race in their opinion, the clearest evidence that the death penalty constituted excessive punishment for
rape was its racially discriminatory imposition: African Americans accounted for about 90% of the defendants executed nationwide for
rape during the period between 1930 and 1967, but for less than 50%
24
of those executed for murder.
The Court’s message spurred the NAACP’s Legal Defense Fund
(“LDF”) to increased action on the death penalty, and the LDF’s
principal argument against the death penalty focused on its arbitrary
and discriminatory use. From the LDF’s perspective, limitation or
abolition of the death penalty was part of the same project to improve
the rights of African American criminal defendants in the South—the
persistence of the death penalty was yet another manifestation of the
distinctive form of Southern justice.
In response to the Court’s opinion, the LDF funded empirical research to document the influence of race in capital sentencing for
25
rape. The LDF also embarked on a more ambitious “moratorium”
26
strategy to end executions in the United States. The moratorium
strategy was rooted in the belief that the death penalty had essentially
run its course. Executions had declined substantially and become
even more geographically confined, and public opinion, especially in
the wake of the Vietnam War, was skeptical of governmental power to
end life. A 1966 Gallup Poll revealed for the first—and only—time

22
23
24
25
26

Robinson v. California, 370 U.S. 660 (1962) (holding that imprisonment for status of being an addict constituted cruel and unusual punishment).
Rudolph v. Alabama, 375 U.S. 889 (1963) (Goldberg, Douglas, and Brennan, JJ., dissenting from denial of certiorari).
MICHAEL MELTSNER, CRUEL AND UNUSUAL: THE SUPREME COURT AND CAPITAL
PUNISHMENT 75 (1973).
See id. at 75–78.
Id. at 107.

164

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

that more Americans opposed than supported the death penalty as
27
punishment for murder.
The moratorium strategy was facilitated by the Court’s recognition
of new criminal protections in state proceedings, but the LDF also
raised new challenges distinctive to the death penalty. These claims
centered on three features of American capital punishment: the
practice of excluding jurors with any reservations about the death
penalty from capital juries, the failure of capital jurisdictions to specify the criteria justifying the imposition of death (or life), and the refusal of some states to permit evidence or arguments related solely to
the appropriate punishment (apart from guilt or innocence of the
underlying offense).
Remarkably, the moratorium strategy succeeded, at least as measured by the goal of bringing a halt to executions in the United States.
Beginning in 1967, the United States went almost a decade without
executions, the longest such period in American history. The claims
raised by the LDF shared common themes. First, the death penalty,
though widely available in the United States, had declining support,
and the procedures states used (such as death-qualifying juries and
unitary proceedings) tended to obscure society’s emerging reservations about the death penalty. Second, the broad schemes of death
eligibility and the absence of standards to guide sentencer discretion
had transformed the American death penalty into a national lottery—
there was no reason to believe that the few offenders sentenced to
death were more deserving than the much larger group of offenders
who were spared. Third, the extraordinary discretion afforded capital sentencers at a time of declining support for the death penalty
contributed to its discriminatory (race- and class-based) imposition;
the death penalty could be tolerated in part because of its infrequency coupled with its use only against marginalized populations.
These critiques of the death penalty borrowed from the larger critique of American criminal justice. Too much discretion throughout
the criminal justice system—beginning with the work of police and
extending to the work of prosecutors and juries—contributed to an
inequitable system in which certain groups, particularly racial minorities, enjoyed fewer freedoms and experienced greater punishments
than the rest of society. The Warren Court response on the noncapital side was to craft bright-line rules limiting discretion with the
hope of establishing a general rule of law. On the capital side, the
27

Robert M. Bohm, American Death Penalty Opinion, 1936–1986: An Overview, in THE DEATH
PENALTY IN AMERICA: CURRENT RESEARCH 115, 116 (Robert M. Bohm ed., 1991).

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

165

Warren Court suspected that the death penalty was already on a
course toward extinction and that if capital practices were modified
to ensure equal participation on juries and equal treatment of offenders, the American public would in fact reject the death penalty.
The reform movement culminated with the Court’s invalidation
28
of existing state statutes in Furman v. Georgia. The terse per curiam
opinion for the Court simply declared that “the imposition and carrying out of the death penalty in these cases constitute cruel and un29
usual punishment.” Each of the five Justices who supported the
judgment wrote separate opinions defending this conclusion, and the
common thread of their opinions focused on the arbitrary imposition
of the punishment. Justice Douglas amplified the theme of discrimination, indicating that the prevailing practice which reserved the
death penalty only for the poor and unpopular could not be salvaged
simply because such discrimination was not found on the face of state
30
statutes. Justices Marshall and Brennan went further and argued
that the death penalty could no longer be squared with prevailing
31
standards of decency.
Noticeably absent, from a present perspective, was any serious attention to the problem of wrongful convictions. This paucity of
treatment is especially telling given that the collection of opinions in
Furman constituted the longest decision in the Court’s history at the
time of its issuance. In a time of declining executions (with no executions in the four years preceding the decision), the Court’s focus
was on the rarity of the punishment and the problems associated with
infrequent application of a broadly available sanction. The death
penalty was not deemed abhorrent because of its careless, overzealous, indiscriminate use, but its virtual disuse. As Justice White argued, the death penalty could not possibly serve any valid penological
purpose (such as deterrence or retribution) if it was so seldom im32
posed. Justice White’s critique pointed to the same conclusion advanced by Justices Marshall and Brennan: if the death penalty no
longer secured any obvious social benefits, the punishment was excessive and unnecessary. But Justice White was not prepared to embrace this conclusion as a constitutional matter without giving the
states a chance to reform their systems.

28
29
30
31
32

408 U.S. 238 (1972) (per curiam).
Id. at 239–40.
Id. at 255–56 (Douglas, J., concurring).
Id. at 286 (Brennan, J., concurring); id. at 369 (Marshall, J., concurring).
Id. at 312–13 (White, J., concurring).

166

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

The Furman Court clearly misread the public mood. Given the
option of repealing or reforming their capital statutes, most capital
jurisdictions chose the latter. Many of these states even seemed to
prefer a much broader capital regime (with the promise of many
more executions) by creating mandatory death penalty schemes that
required the imposition of death for murder (and, in some cases,
other offenses). A larger group of states sought to address the problem of unbridled sentencer discretion by specifying “aggravating factors” that would structure the capital sentencing decision. With rising rates of violent crime and the resulting popular backlash against
the Warren Court’s reforms, the states sought to reassert their prerogative to punish murder with death.
When the Court addressed the new statutes in 1976, it upheld the
33
guided discretion statutes and invalidated the mandatory ones. Although the mandatory statutes held out greater promise of addressing one of the central problems Furman had identified—that the
sheer rarity of death sentences and executions rendered its few applications arbitrary and unnecessary—the Court rejected the mandatory
statutes on the ground that they denied offenders individualized
treatment, precluded sentencers from considering relevant mitigating factors, and departed significantly from longstanding American
34
practices. The guided discretion statutes that the Court embraced
raised new problems of their own: although they purported to narrow sentencer discretion by requiring jurors to find an aggravating
circumstance (beyond the plain fact of murder) to impose the death
penalty, they preserved considerable sentencing discretion to withhold the death penalty for virtually any reason. Whereas Furman
condemned the arbitrary and discriminatory results of unfettered
discretion, the 1976 decisions and their progeny viewed discretion as
an unavoidable part of capital sentencing. More importantly, those
decisions appeared to treat the constitutionality of the American
death penalty as turning on whether state statutes sought to guide discretion in a meaningful manner, not on whether states actually

33

See, e.g., Roberts v. Louisiana, 428 U.S. 325 (1976) (invalidating Louisiana’s mandatory
death penalty sentencing scheme); Woodson v. North Carolina, 428 U.S. 280 (1976)
(plurality opinion) (invalidating North Carolina’s mandatory death penalty sentencing
scheme); Jurek v. Texas, 428 U.S. 262 (1976) (upholding Texas’s special issue scheme
against facial challenge); Proffitt v. Florida, 428 U.S. 242 (1976) (upholding Florida’s
guided discretion statute against facial challenge); Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153 (1976)
(upholding Georgia’s guided discretion statute against facial challenge).

34

Woodson, 428 U.S. at 289–301.

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

167

achieved any discernible level of consistency in the application of the
death penalty.
The 1976 decisions stabilized the American death penalty, and
executions resumed shortly thereafter. By the early 1980s, with the
newly declared War on Drugs in response to the influx of crack cocaine and the much higher violent crime rate that accompanied it,
the politics of criminal justice veered markedly away from reform.
Constitutional regulation of criminal practices was widely viewed as
an obstacle to successful anti-crime efforts, and the Warren Court’s
effort to promote social justice through criminal justice reform was
rejected as naïve and misguided. Incarceration rates, both absolute
and per capita, rose sharply, as both the federal government and
states responded to the threat of disorder with increased punitive
measures.
In this context, the Court addressed the most serious challenge to
the death penalty. Just as it had in the 1960s, the LDF sought to expose the role of race in capital sentencing. After soliciting a comprehensive study of the administration of the death penalty in Georgia,
the LDF insisted that sophisticated statistical analysis revealed the
prominent role of race—particularly the race of victims—in capital
punishment decisionmaking. Whereas Furman had relied on suspicions of arbitrariness and discrimination to invalidate the death penalty, the LDF now supplied what appeared to be an empirical demonstration of the race-based administration of capital punishment. The
LDF’s hope was that the Court would not tolerate continued use of
the death penalty in light of such evidence.
35
In 1987, the Court rejected the claim in McCleskey v. Kemp,
though it assumed for purposes of its decision that the study fairly
identified race-based disparities in capital decisionmaking. According to the Court, such disparities were likely the inevitable result of
the constitutionally required discretion in capital cases. Moreover,
the Court was unwilling to treat the death penalty differently than incarceration: if race-based disparities condemned the death penalty,
then they might condemn incarceration as well. According to the
Court, because “[t]he Eighth Amendment is not limited in application to capital punishment, but applies to all penalties[,] . . . . if we
accepted McCleskey’s claim that racial bias has impermissibly tainted
the capital sentencing decision, we could soon be faced with similar
36
claims as to other types of penalty.”
35
36

481 U.S. 279 (1987).
Id. at 315 (citations omitted).

168

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

McCleskey marked not only the end of arbitrariness- or discrimination-based challenges the death penalty, but also highlighted the importance of framing constitutional challenges to the death penalty in
uniquely capital terms. Given the Court’s increased hostility to Warren Court supervision of criminal justice policies and its decreased
enthusiasm for policing the fairness of the non-capital system, attacks
on capital practices had to prevent spillage over to the non-capital
side.
In the wake of McCleskey, with the Court’s rejection of what
seemed to be the last global challenge to the American death penalty,
executions increased substantially and the death penalty as a practice
seemed secure for at least another generation. Death-sentencing
rates rose to modern era highs in the mid-1990s, and executions went
from about eighteen per year nationwide in the last half of the 1980s
37
to about sixty-six per year in the late 1990s. Previously abolitionist
New York joined the ranks of death penalty states in 1995, and the
Oklahoma City bombing resulted in congressional legislation intended to accelerate executions.
B. A New Reformist Era Focusing on Wrongful Convictions
But public and professional opinion seemed to shift quickly and
dramatically with the discovery of numerous wrongful convictions in
Illinois. The issue emerged as lawyers and journalists uncovered
more than a dozen cases of innocents who had been erroneously sen38
tenced to death. In one particularly alarming case, the inmate, Anthony Porter, had come perilously close to execution before journal39
The
ism students exposed the actual perpetrator of the crime.
circumstances of his case and the post-conviction investigation made
clear that it was entirely a matter of fortuity that Porter had not been
executed before his innocence had been established. A broader investigation into Illinois capital practices revealed numerous systemic
defects, including prosecutorial misconduct. As these defects came
to light, George Ryan, the Republican Governor, declared a moratorium on executions and ultimately commuted the sentences of the
167 inmates on Illinois’ death row. Ryan developed a national reputation as a crusader against wrongful convictions (though he was later
37
38

39

See Executions by Year, supra note 1.
See Ronald J. Tabak, Finality Without Fairness: Why We Are Moving Towards Moratoria on Executions, and the Potential Abolition of Capital Punishment, 33 CONN. L. REV. 733, 739–41
(2001).
Id. at 739.

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

169

prosecuted for and convicted of unrelated corruption), and the
events in Illinois prompted other states to reexamine their capital systems.
The newfound skepticism about the accuracy of convictions was
reinforced by the emerging use of new DNA technology to uncover
wrongful convictions (both capital and non-capital). The capacity of
such technology to expose error was vividly illustrated with the 2000
publication of Actual Innocence: Five Days to Execution and Other Dis40
patches From the Wrongly Convicted, which detailed the successful efforts of Barry Scheck and Peter Neufeld in their pioneering use of
DNA to exonerate convicted capital and non-capital inmates. These
and other DNA exonerations fueled public concerns about the fallibility of our criminal justice system.
Concerns about wrongful convictions generated two types of reform. First, states enacted backward-looking provisions authorizing
post-conviction DNA testing in cases where genetic material is available and new technology could cast doubt on the reliability of the existing conviction; many states also established compensation funds for
those wrongly convicted and exonerated through post-conviction testing. Second, states have looked closely at the sources of error in the
wrongful conviction cases and considered some reforms to prevent
such errors in the future. The wrongful conviction cases provide a
promising starting point to “audit” prevailing investigative and prosecutorial practices, and they have revealed some common sources of
error: misidentification by eyewitnesses, inappropriate reliance on
“junk” forensic science, misuse of jailhouse informant testimony, and
the exaction and use of false confessions, especially in cases involving
youthful or mentally disabled suspects.
To date, although many states have enthusiastically embraced the
“backward-looking” reforms providing for post-conviction access to
DNA testing and for compensation in cases of wrongful conviction,
few have actually reformed their systems regarding the investigation
41
and prosecution of crime. Only a handful of states have altered

40

JIM DWYER ET AL., ACTUAL INNOCENCE: FIVE DAYS TO EXECUTION AND OTHER DISPATCHES
(2000).
Compare
Innocence
Project,
Reforms
by
State,
http://www.innocenceproject.org/news/LawView1.php (last visited Nov. 5, 2008) (showing
states
that
have
adopted
compensation
schemes),
and
http://www.innocenceproject.org/news/LawView2.php (last visited Nov. 5, 2008) (showing states that provide access to DNA testing), with Innocence Project, Reforms by State,
http://www.innocenceproject.org/news/LawView3.php (last visited Nov. 5, 2008) (showing
states
that
require
recorded
interrogations),
and

FROM THE WRONGLY CONVICTED

41

170

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

their policies regarding the recording of interrogations, embraced
new procedures for eyewitness identifications, or created criminal justice reform commissions to prevent wrongful convictions in the fu42
ture. Given the relatively small number of actual DNA exonerees
over the past decade or so (somewhere between 200 and 250), and
the reluctant embrace of related criminal justice reform by states, it
appears that the innocence “revolution” has had much less practical
significance for incarcerated inmates than for the American death
penalty.
On the capital side, concerns about executing the innocent may
have contributed to the precipitous and astonishing drop in capital
sentences over the past eight years. Moreover, concerns about
wrongful executions have no doubt contributed to the palpable shift
in momentum from expansion to contraction of capital punishment
within the United States. Whereas the 1980s and 1990s saw many
states expand their categories of death-eligible offenses and revamp
their procedures to facilitate increased executions, the post-Illinois
experience has produced increased circumspection about capital
punishment. States have entertained—and in some instances embraced—serious proposals to enhance accuracy in capital cases, to
halt executions pending further study, and to abolish the death penalty altogether. Indeed, New York declined to revive its death penalty
after its courts found correctible errors in the state capital statute,
and New Jersey recently joined the cohort of abolitionist states
through legislative abolition. Executions have declined dramatically
(2007 saw fewer than half the number of executions nationwide than
43
were conducted in 2000), propelled by a judicially-enforced national
moratorium on executions in the wake of litigation surrounding the
constitutionality of existing lethal injection protocols.
Moreover, concern about wrongful convictions has surfaced in
several high-profile judicial opinions, suggesting that the courts have
recognized the emerging power of such an appeal in restraining the
reach of the death penalty. In 2002, a federal district judge in New
York found the federal death penalty unconstitutional because of the
excessive risk of wrongful convictions (though the decision was

42
43

http://www.innocenceproject.org/news/LawView5.php (last visited Nov. 5, 2008) (showing states that have reformed eyewitness identification procedures), and
http://www.innocenceproject.org/news/LawView6.php (last visited Nov. 5, 2008) (showing states with criminal justice reform commissions).
See supra note 41.
Executions by Year, supra note 1.

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL
44

171
45

quickly reversed by the Court of Appeals). In Kansas v. Marsh, a
relatively insignificant case focusing on a highly technical issue within
Kansas’s capital statute, four Justices joined a remarkable dissent
highlighting the risk of wrongful capital convictions. Marsh addressed whether a state statute can require jurors to impose death
where the aggravating and mitigating factors in the case are in equipoise. At the time the issue reached the Court, Kansas had a death
row population under ten and had not executed any offenders in
over four decades. The Court’s majority opinion was unremarkable,
holding that previous cases permit the death penalty to be imposed
in such circumstances. Justice Souter’s dissent, joined by three other
Justices, developed a sustained critique of the American death penalty in light of the recent documentation of wrongful convictions.
According to Justice Souter, the uncovering of pervasive error in
capital cases amounts to a “new body of fact [that] must be accounted
for in deciding what, in practical terms, the Eighth Amendment
46
guarantees should tolerate.” His dissent recounts the experience in
Illinois, discusses the role of DNA in identifying innocents on death
row, and offers statistics about the number of “exonerated” inmates
in recent years. In light of such evidence, Justice Souter argues for a
new death penalty principle that would invalidate any state procedures that unnecessarily increase the risk of error in capital cases.
Just as the challenged Kansas procedure allowed “ties” to generate
death sentences, Justice Souter seemed to advocate for a new rule of
capital jurisprudence that invalidates any questionable state procedural policies in capital cases.
Justice Souter’s opinion seems self-consciously designed to bring
the public debate about the reliability of the American death penalty
into the Court’s jurisprudence. This approach is markedly different
from the Furman-era focus on the arbitrary and discriminatory character of the administration of the death penalty. Indeed, a little over
a decade before Marsh, the Court seemed notably unmoved by the
claim that the risk of error in capital cases requires special postconviction procedures to prevent the execution of the innocent: the
Court refused to recognize a due process right to a judicial forum to
47
present newly discovered evidence of innocence in capital cases.

44
45
46
47

United States v. Quinones, 196 F. Supp. 2d 416 (S.D.N.Y. 2002), rev’d, 313 F.3d 49 (2d
Cir. 2002).
548 U.S. 163 (2006).
Id. at 207–08 (Souter, J., dissenting).
Herrera v. Collins, 506 U.S. 390 (1993).

172

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

Moreover, Justice Souter’s opinion is sweeping in its potential. He
insists that the events in Illinois and elsewhere have ushered in a “pe48
riod of new empirical argument about how ‘death is different,’” and
his declaration that “it is far too soon for any generalizations about
49
the soundness of capital sentencing across the country” seems to
signal that such generalizations may well be on the horizon.
More recently, Justice Stevens, who co-authored the joint opinion
reviving the death penalty in the wake of Furman (but who joined Justice Souter’s dissent in Marsh), announced his view that the American
death penalty has essentially run its course and can no longer be
squared with the Constitution. In so doing, Justice Stevens joined
three of his retired colleagues (Justices Brennan, Marshall, and
Blackmun) in declaring that the death penalty had become unconstitutional, though he indicated that he would not act on his view until
an appropriate case raised the issue. In this respect, Justice Stevens,
like Justice Souter, chose a somewhat odd vehicle to issue broad pronouncements respecting the death penalty: Justice Stevens an50
nounced his new view in Baze v. Rees, the case upholding prevailing
lethal injection protocols against constitutional challenge. Justice
Stevens concurred in the result, though he also suggested that states
wishing to avoid further constitutional and practical difficulties
51
“would do well” to reconsider their current protocols.
Justice Stevens then offered a lengthy critique of American capital
punishment, insisting that the retention of the death penalty by various actors (including state legislatures, Congress, and the U.S. Supreme Court itself) was, in his view, the “product of habit and inattention rather than an acceptable deliberative process that weighs the
costs and risks of administering that penalty against its identifiable
52
benefits.” Justice Stevens detailed numerous defects in the American system of capital punishment, including its diminishing or unproven contribution to any valid penological goals (including deterrence or retribution), its arbitrary and discriminatory use, and its
reliance on skewed jury pools for its continued viability. But the factor Justice Stevens identified as of “decisive importance” was its irrevocability, coupled with the recent experience of an “unacceptable

48
49
50
51
52

Marsh, 548 U.S. at 210 (Souter, J., dissenting).
Id.
128 S. Ct. 1520 (2008).
Id. at 1546 (Stevens, J., concurring).
Id.

Dec. 2008]

173

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL
53

number” of defendants wrongfully convicted of capital murder. According to Justice Stevens, “[t]he risk of executing innocent defendants can be entirely eliminated by treating any penalty more severe
than life imprisonment without the possibility of parole as constitu54
tionally excessive.”
Thus, the problem of wrongful convictions has tipped the scales
for at least one member of the Court from constitutional permissibility to constitutional violation. The Stevens concurrence in Baze and
the Souter dissent in Marsh suggest that the innocence revolution
might provide the framework for the ultimate judicial abolition of the
death penalty, a prospect that seemed remote at best not more than a
decade ago.
Notwithstanding the apparent popular and political traction of
the wrongful conviction issue, and its potential leverage in constitutional adjudication in restraining or abolishing the death penalty, we
have previously expressed concerns about the potential costs of an
55
innocence focus in capital law and advocacy. First, we rejected the
claim that executing innocents is categorically different from a range
of other harms that are present in the capital punishment system.
Moreover, we maintained that these latter problems—including the
arbitrary and discriminatory administration of the death penalty and
the execution of guilty but undeserving or impaired offenders—are
56
far more ubiquitous than the problem of wrongful executions. We
also feared that an innocence focus in the capital context might overshadow or affirmatively undermine other important critiques of the
American death penalty, including challenges based on claims of
57
fairness or human dignity. Lastly, we lamented the potential of the
innocence revolution to undermine traditional public defense values
by bolstering the message that actual innocence is the true measure
of a defendant’s worthiness of representation (as illustrated by new
innocence projects that explicitly condition representation on a col58
orable claim of actual innocence).
Despite these concerns, we remain unsure whether the new focus
on innocence marks the first substantial step down the path to abolition or whether it is a transient phenomenon sustained by an unusual

53
54
55
56
57
58

Id. at 1551.
Id.
See Steiker & Steiker, supra note 8, at 607–23.
Id. at 606.
Id. at 615–16.
Id. at 618–21.

174

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

confluence of social and political factors (including stable or declining violent crime rates, an unpopular war, and growing skepticism
about the benign character of government). Given the legal landscape prevailing just five or ten years ago, we would not have expected the questions surrounding wrongful convictions to have surfaced as quickly and as powerfully as they recently have in the Souter
and Stevens opinions discussed above. These decisions suggest that
the innocence revolution might well have significance for the constitutional status of the death penalty—an undoubtedly extraordinary
development.
Here, though, we raise slightly different concerns about the innocence revolution. The transformative capacity of the innocence revolution on the capital side—its potential to reform or abolish the
death penalty—seems much greater than its capacity to improve or
transform our non-capital system. As noted above, the legislative reaction to the problem of wrongful convictions has focused primarily
on post-hoc DNA testing and compensation for the wrongfully convicted. Broad reform of investigative and prosecutorial practices has
been tentative and more controversial. Whereas numerous advocates, public officials, and judges regard the fallibility of the death
penalty as a plausible ground for its rejection, no one regards the fact
of wrongful convictions as a basis for jettisoning incarceration. The
prospect of wrongful convictions becomes a basis for increasing our
reliance on incarceration and reducing executions, not necessarily a
basis for reducing incarceration overall.
Perhaps more importantly, many of the costs of an innocence focus are even more acute on the non-capital side. Over the past three
decades, we have embarked on an unprecedented experiment with
mass incarceration. The jail and prison population of the United
States has grown eight-fold over the past thirty-five years. In addition
to imprisoning the most inmates in absolute terms worldwide, the
United States also has an incarceration rate that is five to eight times
higher than other Western industrialized nations; we have recently
achieved the dubious distinction of imprisoning more than one out
of every hundred American adults. Much of the expansion of the
prison population is attributable to more punitive sentencing regimes, especially for non-violent offenders. National spending on incarceration has reached unprecedented levels, with estimates that
states and the federal government spend over $65 billion annually to
house the more than 2.3 million inmates held nationwide. Moreover,
the rate of incarceration in minority populations is particularly high,

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

175

with one in nine black males between the ages of 20 and 34 behind
bars.
Despite the enormous social and political costs of our mass incarceration policies, reform efforts have been unable to reverse the remarkable trends. We fear that the presence of the death penalty, as
well as the focus on actual innocence, undermines the prospects for
non-capital reform. First, the innocence critique tends to focus on
the selection of those to be incarcerated rather than on the pathologies of incarceration policy. Tinkering with the investigation and
prosecution of crime will leave untouched the prevailing punitive
framework. The one important link between wrongful convictions
and excessive punitiveness is frequently missed in public and professional debate: the presence of extremely harsh sanctions encourages
plea-bargaining, and when the plea-bargain discount is sufficiently
high, excessive punishments encourage the innocent to plead guilty.
But few advocates of reform have sought to attack the problem of
wrongful convictions by reducing the harshness of our current sanctions. Second, the focus on innocence also tends to legitimate and
entrench the justice of harshly punishing the guilty. Likewise, the
more precariously held values of fairness, non-discrimination, adequate representation and procedural regularity are endangered by
equating “injustice” with inaccuracy.
Apart from the focus on innocence, current abolitionist advocacy
tends to reinforce rather than question increasingly punitive sanctions. This dynamic is most evident in death penalty opponents’ support for harsh incarceration sanctions (including LWOP) as a way of
undermining support for the death penalty. In this respect, abolitionists deflect arguments about the ways in which lengthy incarceration (and the absence of alternative sanctions) undermines human
dignity: lengthy incarceration is viewed as a “lesser” evil instead of as
an evil in itself.
It remains unclear whether and to what extent opposition to the
death penalty has facilitated the now near-universal embrace of lifewithout-possibility-of-parole in American jurisdictions. LWOP is an
extraordinarily recent phenomenon, and its adoption coincided with
both the rise in violent crime rates and the destabilitization of the
59
death penalty that began in the 1970s. Some states clearly adopted
LWOP in direct response to the Court’s constitutional regulation of
the death penalty: Alabama, Illinois, and Louisiana adopted such
59

Note, A Matter of Life and Death: The Effect of Life-Without-Parole Statutes on Capital Punishment, 119 HARV. L. REV. 1838, 1840–41 (2006).

176

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

statutes for the first time in response to Furman, fearing that the abolition of the death penalty would leave no other means of protecting
60
the community from violent murderers.
But LWOP has also
61
emerged in virtually all capital and non-capital jurisdictions, making
it difficult to understand LWOP merely as an alternative to death.
In some jurisdictions, however, the connection between anti-death
penalty advocacy and the adoption of LWOP is unmistakable. In
Texas, for example, death penalty opponents long sought the adoption of LWOP as the alternative punishment to death in cases of capital murder. Texas prosecutors, fearing that the LWOP alternative
would reduce the prospects for death verdicts, consistently and vigorously opposed the LWOP alternative. Only after the Court invalidated the death penalty as applied to juvenile offenders were death
penalty opponents able to overcome prosecutorial resistance, and
only because prosecutors now viewed LWOP as increasing rather than
62
decreasing the maximum punishment available for juveniles.
The benefits and costs of the abolitionist embrace of LWOP are
uncertain. Abolitionists clearly believe that the LWOP alternative will
reduce use of the death penalty, and opinion polls consistently show
significantly lower support for the death penalty where LWOP is offered as an alternative punishment. Moreover, the astonishing decline in death sentencing over the past decade is likely attributable in
part to the increased availability of LWOP as an alternative sentenc63
ing option.
But the obvious cost of this abolitionist strategy is to normalize
and legitimate LWOP as a punishment. And the number of poten-

60
61

62
63

Id. at 1841.
Every state but New Mexico and Alaska currently permits the imposition of LWOP. See
Death
Penalty
Information
Center,
Life
Without
Parole,
http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/life-without-parole.
The developments in Texas are recounted in A Matter of Life and Death, supra note 59, at
1843–44.
See id. at 1850 (arguing that the enactment of LWOP statutes is correlated with a small
decrease in death sentences). We believe that the correlation might be greater than suggested by this article because the author focuses on whether declines in death sentences
were immediately realized after the adoption of LWOP. The most significant reason for
the enormous decline in death sentences over the past decade is the willingness of prosecutors to accept pleas to LWOP. We believe that this institutional shift in prosecutorial
attitudes and practices does not happen overnight in response to legislative change, even
if the legislative change in fact permits the shift in policy. Indeed, the presence of LWOP
makes it easier for prosecutors to respond to other concerns about the death penalty (e.g.,
the possibility of wrongful convictions) with greater willingness to accept pleas, because
fear of a defendant’s eventual release is often the biggest obstacle to persuading victims’
families to support a negotiated settlement.

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

177

tially death-sentenced defendants spared because of the LWOP alternative pales in comparison to the enormous number of non-deatheligible inmates who are now without hope of parole because of
64
LWOP’s widespread adoption. Anti-death penalty advocacy may not
be wholly responsible for the widespread entrenchment of LWOP,
but it certainly undermines the emergence of a progressive assault on
the practice. Unless and until the death penalty is abolished, LWOP
will be embraced by many progressive criminal justice reformers as a
necessary but regrettable alternative to the perceived greater evil.
II. DOCTRINAL WALL-BUILDING
It should not be surprising that the distinctiveness of capital litigation produces legal doctrine that has different salience in capital versus non-capital litigation. After all, if the special context of capital
punishment creates distinctive incentives in the arena of advocacy, as
discussed above, we should expect the results of that advocacy—
whether in judicially created constitutional doctrine or legislation—
to reflect the same potentially troubling double edge. Though there
are many examples, large and small, of ways in which the distinctiveness of capital punishment law might redound to the detriment of
ordinary criminal defendants, here we will highlight three of the
most significant and overarching areas. The first—constitutional limits on excessive punishment—is an example of a single constitutional
provision (the Eighth Amendment’s proscription of cruel and unusual punishments) that has resulted in two formally distinct lines of
doctrine in the capital and non-capital contexts. The second—the
constitutional regulation of the effectiveness of defense counsel—is
an example of a doctrine that does not purport to distinguish formally between capital and non-capital cases, but that nonetheless has
distinctive consequences in the two contexts. The third—judicial and
legislative revamping of the scope of federal habeas corpus review—is
an example of the “specialness” of capital punishment leading to narrowed protection for all convicted offenders, rather than to special
protections limited only to capital defendants. Each of these areas of
law offers insight into how the settled acceptance that “death is different” may obscure or normalize pathologies that afflict non-capital
criminal punishment.

64

Id. at 1851–52 (detailing the extraordinary increase of state inmates sentenced to LWOP
in recent years, including inmates otherwise ineligible for the death penalty).

178

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

A. Constitutional Proportionality Doctrine
The divergence of constitutional doctrine in capital and noncapital cases is nowhere more evident than in the Supreme Court’s
treatment of excessive or disproportionate punishment under the
Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause of the Eighth Amendment.
Though the Court has recognized that the Eighth Amendment places
substantive limits on both capital and non-capital punishments, the
Court has developed two distinct lines of doctrine for the two different contexts. Indeed, these two lines of doctrine have diverged radically from their common constitutional origins in the Eighth
Amendment, remaining virtually hermetically sealed from each other
and resulting in two quite differently demanding thresholds for judicial invalidation of legislatively sanctioned punishment.
Consider first the development of the Court’s proportionality doctrine in capital cases. Just one year after the Court reauthorized capi65
tal punishment in Gregg v. Georgia and its accompanying cases (rejecting the global claim that capital punishment is in all cases cruel
and unusual punishment), the Court invalidated the death penalty as
being a disproportionate punishment for the particular crime of the
66
rape of an adult woman in Coker v. Georgia. In Coker, the four-person
plurality opinion established the basic framework that the Court has
used ever since—though with some important recent refinements—
for considering claims that the imposition of the death penalty constitutes “excessive” punishment under the circumstances. Insisting
that the Court’s judgment of the excessiveness of a punishment
“should be informed by objective factors to the maximum possible
67
extent,” the Coker plurality sought “guidance in history and from the
objective evidence of the country’s present judgment” about the ac68
ceptability of the death penalty for rape. The plurality first considered the record of state legislation on the issue, noting that at no
point in the fifty years preceding its decision had a majority of states
authorized the death penalty for the rape of an adult woman. Moreover, at the moment of its decision, the state of Georgia was the only
jurisdiction in the country to authorize capital punishment for that
69
particular crime. The plurality then turned its attention to jury de65
66
67
68
69

428 U.S. 153 (1976). See supra note 33 for a list of accompanying cases.
433 U.S. 584 (1977) (plurality opinion).
Id. at 592.
Id. at 593.
Prior to the Court’s decision in Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238 (1972), sixteen states had
authorized capital punishment for the rape of an adult woman, but by 1977, Georgia was

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

179

cisions in capital rape sentencings, noting that Georgia juries had
imposed the death penalty for rape only six times since Furman, a
number that represented less than 10% of all rape sentencings during that period. Finally, the plurality explained that consideration of
objective evidence is only part of the required Eighth Amendment
analysis, “for the Constitution contemplates that in the end our own
judgment will be brought to bear on the question of the acceptability
70
of the death penalty under the Eighth Amendment.” Here, the plurality emphasized that rape, in contrast to murder, does not end life:
“Life is over for the victim of the murderer; for the rape victim, life
may not be nearly so happy as it was, but it is not over and normally is
71
not beyond repair.”
Five years later, Justice White, the author of the Coker plurality
72
opinion, wrote for a majority of the Court in Enmund v. Florida, applying Coker’s methodology to invalidate the death penalty for a defendant who had served as the getaway car driver in a felony murder
but who had neither participated in the killing, nor attempted nor
intended to kill. Once again, the Court considered the number of
jurisdictions (eight) that authorized capital punishment under these
circumstances and the number of such defendants (three) whom juries had actually sentenced to death in the post-Furman era. The
Court elaborated a bit on its criteria, appearing to create a hierarchy
among legislative data by noting particularly that none of the eight
most recently enacted death penalty statutes authorized use of the penalty in such circumstances. Moreover, the Court acknowledged that
prosecutorial charging decisions (though harder to document than
jury verdicts) also constitute relevant objective evidence of changing
societal values. And the Court counted actual executions in addition

70
71

72

alone. The state of Georgia and the Coker dissenters argued, with some plausibility, that
the precipitous decline in such statutes reflected some states’ attempts to respond to
Furman by passing mandatory capital statutes, which required them to narrow capital
categories more than they might otherwise have done. The majority acknowledged that
this dynamic may have played some role in the decline, but concluded that it was not a
large enough role to overcome the overwhelming lopsidedness of the snapshot count of
current state legislation (forty-nine to one). See Coker, 433 U.S. at 595.
Coker, 433 U.S. at 597.
Id. at 598. The Court recently extended its holding in Coker to include the rape of children, striking down a Louisiana statute allowing the death penalty for child rapists. Kennedy v. Louisiana, 128 S. Ct. 2641 (2008). The analysis in Kennedy closely tracked that of
Coker and of the Court’s more recent decisions in Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S. 304 (2002),
and Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551 (2005). See infra text accompanying notes 80–97.
458 U.S. 782 (1982).

180

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

to jury verdicts, remarking that there had been no executions of nontriggerman felony murderers since 1955.
In bringing its own judgment to bear (“it is for us ultimately to
73
judge” ), the Court noted that Enmund, like Coker, had not actually
taken a life. Here, too, the Court further elaborated, considering
whether the use of the death penalty in this context measurably contributed to either of the “two principal social purposes” of capital
punishment—“retribution and deterrence of capital crimes by pro74
spective offenders.”
Deterrence failed as a justification for Enmund’s punishment, reasoned the Court, because the threat that the
death penalty will be imposed for murder will not deter those who do
not kill or intend to take life. Moreover, retribution failed because
Enmund’s lack of intent suggested that his criminal culpability
should be limited to his participation in the underlying felony (a
robbery) rather than extend to the murder committed by codefendants more culpable than he.
Although the Court modified the Enmund holding five years later
75
in Tison v. Arizona, it nonetheless reaffirmed its Coker/Enmund
methodology. The Tison Court emphasized that the legislative head
count had been altered by “substantial and recent legislative authorization of the death penalty for the crime of felony murder regardless
76
of the absence of a finding of an intent to kill” and that the jury verdict picture had been altered by the willingness of state courts to im77
pose and uphold death sentences even absent findings of intent. In
bringing its own judgment to bear, the Court explained that the
mental state of reckless disregard for human life was equivalent in
moral culpability to an intent to kill and noted that both the common
law and the Model Penal Code treated a high degree of recklessness
78
as a legal equivalent to intent in their definitions of murder.
The Court’s story of Eighth Amendment restrictions on the substantive scope of the death penalty seemed to come to a close in
1989, when the Court rejected two key challenges to the scope of the
death penalty, upholding capital punishment for juvenile offenders

73
74
75

76
77
78

Id. at 797.
Id. at 798 (quoting Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153, 183 (1976)).
481 U.S. 137 (1987) (authorizing under the Constitution capital punishment for nontriggerman felony murderers who played a substantial role in the underlying felony and
evinced reckless disregard for human life).
Id. at 154.
Id. at 154–55.
Id. at 157.

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

181

79

and for offenders with mental retardation. More than a dozen years
passed without any further discussion by the Court of Eighth
Amendment capital proportionality. Then, in its recent opinions in
80
81
Atkins v. Virginia and Roper v. Simmons, overturning the 1989 decisions, the Court endorsed the basic structure of its prior Eighth
Amendment proportionality doctrine while radically expanding the
scope of relevant considerations. In Atkins, the Court held that the
death penalty may not constitutionally be imposed on offenders with
mental retardation. It framed its analysis in the now-familiar terms of
its prior capital proportionality cases, first considering “objective evidence” of national consensus and then bringing its “own judgment”
to bear “by asking whether there is reason to disagree with the judg82
ment reached by the citizenry and its legislators.”
On the straight numbers alone, Atkins did not look like a strong
case for the existence of a national consensus against executing offenders with mental retardation. Of the thirty-eight states that retained the death penalty, only eighteen explicitly forbade the practice.
The Court noted several key facts in support of its
characterization of this head count as a consensus. First, the Court
counted the twelve abolitionist states as states opposing the practice
of executing offenders with mental retardation. Second, the Court
noted that sixteen of the eighteen retentionist states that prohibited
the practice had passed legislation doing so within the past dozen
years: “It is not so much the number of these States that is signifi83
cant, but the consistency of the direction of change.” The Court observed both the generally unpopular nature of statutory protections
for violent criminals and the overwhelming legislative support for the
particular protection at issue (that is, the balance of votes for and
against) in the legislatures that passed the ban. To this evidence of a
legislative trend, the Court added the fact that only a relatively low
number of states (five) actually performed executions of offenders
with mental retardation in the almost thirteen years since Penry.
Most controversially, the Court added in a footnote that
“[a]dditional evidence makes it clear that this legislative judgment re-

79

80
81
82
83

Stanford v. Kentucky, 492 U.S. 361 (1989) (finding no constitutional bar to the execution
of juvenile offenders); Penry v. Lynaugh, 492 U.S. 302 (1989) (finding no constitutional
bar to the execution of offenders with mental retardation).
536 U.S. 304 (2002).
543 U.S. 551 (2005).
536 U.S. at 312–13.
Id. at 315.

182

[Vol. 11:1

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW
84

flects a much broader social and professional consensus.” This additional evidence consisted of the official positions of “several organiza85
tions with germane expertise,” the views of “widely diverse religious
86
87
communities,” the practices of “the world community,” and domes88
tic polling data.
The Court stated that “these factors are by no
means dispositive,” but explained that “their consistency with the legislative evidence lends further support to our conclusion that there is
89
a consensus among those who have addressed the issue.”
Turning from objective evidence of consensus to its own view, the
Court considered “the relationship between mental retardation and
90
the penological purposes served by the death penalty.” As in Enmund, the Court limited itself to two purposes: retribution and deterrence. The Court found that neither purpose would be measurably
advanced by the execution of offenders with mental retardation. As
for retribution, the Court concluded that the cognitive deficiencies
that characterize offenders with mental retardation diminish their
personal culpability so as to exclude them from the category of those
91
“most deserving of execution.” As for deterrence, the Court found
that the limited ability of offenders with mental retardation to “process the information of the possibility of execution as a penalty and, as
92
a result, control their conduct based upon that information” suggested that executing such offenders would not measurably further
the goal of deterrence. Finally, the Court’s own view was informed by
procedural considerations regarding the risk of wrongful conviction
as well—notably the greater likelihood that defendants with mental
retardation might falsely confess, or that they might make poor witnesses at trial or sentencing, or that they might generate fears about
their future dangerousness in light of their disability.
The Court emphatically underscored its Atkins analysis three years
93
later in Simmons, overturning its 1989 Stanford decision that had
permitted the execution of juvenile offenders. The Court once again
emphasized both objective evidence and the bringing of its own
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93

Id. at 316 n.21.
Id. (citing amicus briefs from the American Psychological Association and the American
Association on Mental Retardation).
Id. (citing amicus briefs from the United States Catholic Conference, et al.).
Id. at 317 n.21 (citing amicus brief from the European Union).
Id. (citing both state and national polls).
Id.
Id. at 317.
Id. at 319.
Id. at 320.
543 U.S. 551 (2005).

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

183

judgment to bear, explicitly overruling the Stanford Court’s rejection
of the relevance of the Court’s independent judgment. The objective
numbers in Simmons were almost identical to those in Atkins—
eighteen of thirty-eight states prohibited the execution of juvenile offenders, and only six states had carried out executions of juvenile offenders in the years since Stanford (and only three states in the previous decade). The Simmons claim was weaker than that in Atkins,
though, because fewer of the bans on executing juvenile offenders
were very recent: there had been significantly less change on the
ground since 1989, and thus it was harder to discern a newly emerging consensus. Nonetheless, the Court found such a consensus, observing that it would be “the ultimate in irony” to decline to find a
consensus when the slower pace of change in the juvenile context was
due to the earlier recognition of the inappropriateness of executing
94
juveniles.
But the Court gave the most sustained treatment to its analysis applying “its own judgment.” The Court relied on important differences between juvenile and adult offenders to conclude that juveniles
do not belong in the category of the “worst” offenders, in the sense of
the most deserving. The Court invoked both “scientific and socio95
logical studies” and what “any parent knows” to draw a portrait of
juvenile offenders as more impulsive, immature, irresponsible, and
susceptible to negative influences, while at the same time more likely
to change and mature over time, than adult offenders. These qualities, concluded the Court, make juveniles both less deserving (from a
retributive perspective) of society’s most severe sanction and less
likely to be susceptible to deterrence. The Court also moved part of
its controversial footnote 21 from Atkins into text in Simmons, offering
a full-throated defense of the relevance of the views and practices of
other nations. Noting that the United States was alone in the world
in officially authorizing the execution of juvenile offenders, the Court
firmly declared: “The opinion of the world community, while not
controlling our outcome, does provide respected and significant con96
firmation for our own conclusions.”
Though most famous and controversial for its defense of the relevance of world opinion, the Supreme Court’s recent exposition of its
capital proportionality doctrine in Atkins and Simmons is notable for

94
95
96

Id. at 567 (quoting State ex rel. Simmons v. Roper, 112 S.W.3d 397, 408 n.10 (Mo. 2003)
(en banc) (reaching the same conclusion)).
Id. at 569.
Id. at 578.

184

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

our purposes—that is, in comparison to non-capital proportionality
doctrine—in several other ways as well. First, the cases are striking
simply for their results—the reversal of two relatively recent precedents, and the finding of national consensus against a particular
death penalty practice in the face of disagreement by a majority of
states that retained the death penalty. Second, the Court’s approach
to the question of consensus makes relevant a radically more expansive range of information than earlier capital proportionality cases,
ranging from more qualitative information about legislative change
(its currentness, speed, degree of support, etc.) to information about
the views of elites (experts, religious leaders, political elites abroad,
etc.). Finally, the Court’s “own judgment” is shaped by considering
two—and only two—recognized purposes of capital punishment, retribution and deterrence. The crucial exclusion of incapacitation
from this list permits a plausible finding that the death penalty is inappropriate even for categories of offenders that include those who
appear to pose a substantial risk of future danger.
The Court’s development of its non-capital proportionality doctrine over the same thirty-year period provides a study in sharp contrasts, despite the fact that the two doctrines derive from the same
constitutional provision and draw upon the same foundational cases.
In both the capital and non-capital contexts, the Court almost always
begins its constitutional analysis by paying lip service to Weems v.
97
98
United States and Trop v. Dulles, two non-capital cases that established that the Eighth Amendment prohibits excessive punishments
that offend “the evolving standards of decency that mark the progress
99
of a maturing society.” Yet during the same period that the Court’s
capital proportionality doctrine became more expansive in its scope
of relevant considerations and more generous to criminal defendants
in its outcomes, the Court’s non-capital proportionality doctrine became more limited in its scope of relevant considerations and so deferential to state interests as to make Eighth Amendment challenges
to excessive incarceration essentially non-starters.
In the early 1980s, the Court dealt in quick succession with a series
of cases challenging lengthy prison terms as excessive under the

97
98
99

217 U.S. 349 (1910) (holding that punishment of twelve years jailed in irons at hard and
painful labor for the crime of falsifying records was constitutionally excessive).
356 U.S. 86 (1958) (holding that loss of citizenship by a native-born citizen upon conviction by a court-martial for wartime desertion was constitutionally excessive).
Id. at 101.

Dec. 2008]

185

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL
100

Eighth Amendment. In the first case, Rummel v. Estelle, the Court
upheld a life sentence (with possibility of parole) for a repeat offender convicted of obtaining $120.75 by false pretences, who had
previously been convicted of two even more petty frauds. Over a dissent by Justice Powell, a bare majority of the Court observed that “one
could argue without fear of contradiction by any decision of this
Court that for crimes concededly classified and classifiable as felonies, that is, as punishable by significant terms of imprisonment in a
state penitentiary, the length of the sentence actually imposed is
101
purely a matter of legislative prerogative.” Two years later, in Hutto
102
v. Davis, the Court summarily reversed a grant of habeas relief to a
defendant sentenced to forty years in prison and a fine of $20,000 for
possession and distribution of approximately nine ounces of marijuana, holding that its decision in Rummel clearly doomed Davis’s
103
challenge. A single year later, however, the Court in Solem v. Helm
granted Eighth Amendment relief to a repeat offender who was sentenced to life without possibility of parole for writing a “no account”
check with intent to defraud, despite the fact that Helm had a more
serious criminal history than Rummel (who had been denied relief
three years previously). Justice Powell, who had authored the dissent
in Rummel, now authored the majority opinion in Solem v. Helm, laying
out a proportionality test that, had it prevailed in later cases, would
treat non-capital proportionality challenges roughly similarly to capital proportionality challenges.
Justice Powell’s three-factor test required consideration of: (1)
104
“the gravity of the offense and the harshness of the penalty” ; (2)
“the sentences imposed on other criminals in the same jurisdic105
tion” ; and (3) “the sentences imposed for commission of the same
106
crime in other jurisdictions.” Like the Court’s non-capital proportionality doctrine, this test requires consideration of how “other jurisdictions” treat the same offense; it suggests that the weight or trend
of practice outside of the challenged jurisdiction is highly salient.
Moreover, the test’s requirement that judicial decision-makers weigh
the “gravity” of the offense against the “harshness” of the penalty implicitly requires the articulation of some normative framework for as100
101
102
103
104
105
106

445 U.S. 263 (1980).
Id. at 274.
454 U.S. 370 (1982).
463 U.S. 277 (1983).
Id. at 290–91.
Id. at 291.
Id. at 291–92.

186

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

sessing the fit of crime and punishment; any such assessment will inevitably resemble what the Court calls, in its capital proportionality
cases, bringing its “own judgment” to bear. (The last factor, number
(2) in Justice Powell’s test, is a way of testing fit by reference to a particular jurisdiction’s already articulated normative vision in its treatment of other offenses and offenders.)
Justice Powell’s three-part test in Helm, though not articulated in
the same terms as the capital proportionality cases decided almost
107
simultaneously, invokes the same kind of “objective” evidence (inter-jurisdictional comparison) and “judgment” about proportionality
(gravity weighed against harshness), roughly speaking. But this
rough equivalence did not last long. In its more recent non-capital
cases, the Court sharply narrowed its proportionality analysis, even as
it opened up its capital proportionality analysis. In the very next non108
capital proportionality case after Helm, Harmelin v. Michigan, a majority of the Court rejected Justice Powell’s analysis—or rather, refined it right out of existence. The fractured majority consisted of
two Justices who would have allowed no Eighth Amendment proportionality review in non-capital cases and a three-Justice plurality who
believed that the Eighth Amendment contained a much narrower
proportionality principle than Justice Powell recognized in Helm. According to the plurality, an Eighth Amendment challenge on propor109
tionality grounds can proceed only in the “rare” case in which the
judicial decision-maker discerns a gross disproportionality between
the gravity of the offense and the harshness of the punishment. If a
challenge clears this threshold test, then the judicial decision-maker
may go on to perform the intra- and inter-jurisdictional comparisons
called for by Helm in order to complete the proportionality analysis.
If the threshold test is not met, however, no consideration of the
other two factors is necessary.
The application of this new threshold requirement of gross disproportionality has proven to be an insurmountable hurdle for
Eighth Amendment challenges to long prison terms. In Harmelin itself, the Court upheld against constitutional challenge the imposition
of a mandatory sentence of life without possibility of parole for a firsttime felony offender convicted of possessing 672 grams of cocaine.

107

108
109

Helm was decided in 1983, building on Powell’s Rummel dissent of 1980. See supra notes
100, 102. Coker was decided in 1977, Enmund in 1982, and Tison in 1987. See supra notes
66, 72, 75.
501 U.S. 957 (1991) (plurality opinion).
Id. at 1005.

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

187

Adverting to the gravity of the threats posed by the distribution of illegal drugs, the Court reasoned that Harmelin’s crime “threatened to
110
cause grave harm to society” and that Michigan had “good reason”
111
and “a rational basis” for its extremely harsh treatment of such offenses. The use of the phrase “rational basis” is particularly telling
here, because it echoes the Court’s lowest tier of scrutiny for equal
protection challenges to legislative classifications—challenges that
112
almost never succeed. The Harmelin dissenters, in contrast, demonstrated how the use of inter- and intra-jurisdictional analysis could
make a crucial difference. Looking within the state, the only other
offense (aside from drug offenses) in Michigan for which mandatory
life without possibility of parole was authorized was first-degree murder; in contrast, second-degree murder, rape, and armed robbery did
not carry such a harsh mandatory sentence. Looking to other jurisdictions, the dissenters noted that “[n]o other jurisdiction imposes a
punishment nearly as severe as Michigan’s for possession of the
113
amount of drugs at issue here.”
The difficulty of meeting the gross disproportionality threshold
requirement was underscored by the Court’s most recent application
114
of the test in 2003 in Ewing v. California. Ironically, this case was decided between the Court’s two dramatic applications of its newly
powerful capital proportionality doctrine in Atkins (2002) and Simmons (2005). In Ewing, the Court upheld the operation of California’s “three-strikes-you’re-out” law that resulted in a twenty-five-yearsto-life sentence for a repeat offender convicted of attempting to steal
three golf clubs from a golf course pro shop. In considering whether
the sanction was grossly disproportionate to the offense, the Court insisted that legislatures must remain free to decide for themselves what
purposes they seek to advance in the criminal justice systems. Reasoning that the state of California could reasonably believe that its
harsh law would promote its interest in deterring crime (by inducing
parolees to leave the state) and especially its interest in incapacitating
offenders likely to recidivate, the Court held that Ewing’s was not
“the rare case in which a threshold comparison of the crime commit-

110
111
112

113
114

Id. at 1002.
Id. at 1004.
See generally Robert C. Farrell, Successful Rational Basis Claims in the Supreme Court from the
1971 Term Through Romer v. Evans, 32 IND. L. REV. 357 (1999) (cataloging and attempting to explain the few challenges that have succeeded under the Court’s usually exceedingly deferential rational basis review).
Harmelin, 501 U.S. at 1026 (White, J., dissenting) (emphasis added).
538 U.S. 11 (2003) (plurality opinion).

188

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

ted and the sentence imposed leads to an inference of gross dispro115
portionality.” In a choice of quotation that reveals just how difficult
the non-capital proportionality test is meant to be, the Ewing Court
reached back to repeat approvingly the Rummel Court’s observation
that the proportionality principle would “come into play in the extreme example . . . if a legislature made overtime parking a felony
116
punishable by life imprisonment.”
While the two lines of Eighth Amendment proportionality review
in the capital and non-capital contexts might be thought unremarkable considered separately, their juxtaposition inevitably creates a jarring contrast and generates difficult questions. Why is a national legislative head count the objective touchstone for Eighth Amendment
analysis in capital cases, while consideration of what other jurisdictions do is not even part of the non-capital analysis unless some
enormously high threshold of gross disproportionality is reached
first? Why is constitutional consideration given to elite expert and
world opinion and to trends in practices in the capital context, but
none in non-capital cases? Why is incapacitation recognized as a legitimate purpose of non-capital punishment, but not of capital punishment (when death is surely the only completely reliable means of
incapacitation)? How is it that the most serious drug sentence (by
far) and the harshest “three strikes” statute in the entire country can
withstand non-capital proportionality review, while on the capital
side, a minority of retentionist jurisdictions can outlaw the execution
of juvenile offenders and offenders with mental retardation everywhere? The Court never answers these questions directly. Indeed, it
virtually never makes any explicit comparison between the two lines
of doctrine. Rather, it tends to ritualistically intone some version of
its “death is different” mantra. By implication, the Court seems to be
suggesting that the unique severity and irrevocability of a sentence of
death does and should make such sentences uniquely sensitive to a
more heightened and sensitive proportionality analysis.
The upshot, however, is that the “difference” of death has cabined
searching proportionality review outside of the capital context. One
might argue that the development of more searching proportionality
review on the capital side is actually a boon for all criminal defendants, because the more demanding death penalty doctrine may
eventually spill over into the non-capital side, and, in any case, it pro115

Id. at 30 (quoting Harmelin, 501 U.S. at 1005 (Kennedy, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment)).

116

Id. at 21 (quoting Rummel v. Estelle, 445 U.S. 263, 274 n.11 (1980)).

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

189

vides a template for a more sensitive doctrine by expanding the range
of relevant considerations and demonstrating how they might be deployed. There is no reason why this hopeful (from the perspective of
defendants) prospect could never happen. But exactly the opposite
is what has actually occurred, and there is some reason to think that
the causal influences run exactly contrary to the hopeful view. A
more pessimistic but probably more realistic view is that capital defendants can succeed only on the condition that their success does not
spill over into the non-capital side.
First, the very same reasoning (from reduced culpability relative to
other offenders) that excluded juveniles, offenders with mental retardation, and (some) non-triggermen from the ambit of the death
penalty might also exclude them from the next most serious punishment, especially in jurisdictions that do not authorize capital punishment. For the Court to avoid backlash in response to its narrowing
of the scope of capital punishment (a response with which it is familiar from its early death penalty cases), it needs to ensure that a very
serious punishment remains unassailably available for those whom it
exempts from death. The best way to ensure this availability is to
maintain a different proportionality analysis on the non-capital side.
Second, the number of ordinary criminal defendants is larger, by
orders of magnitude, than the number of capital defendants. Moreover, the range of prison terms and other possible penalties is a
broad continuum on the non-capital side, in contrast to the “on/off”
switch of capital punishment. These two facts together suggest a
much more ominous threat of floodgates opening on the non-capital
side than on the capital side of proportionality litigation. Hence, one
should expect to see exactly what has developed—that any developments in proportionality review on the capital side would be strictly
confined and prevented from generating instability in the much larger and more amorphous arena of ordinary criminal punishment.
But why should a Court that is clearly unwilling to regulate noncapital sentences be so willing to intervene constitutionally on the
capital side? The text and history of the Eighth Amendment certainly
does not call for such a sharp divide (or any divide at all) between
these forms of punishment. One could simply accept at face value
the Court’s repeated observation that “death is different” from all
other punishments in its severity and irrevocability. Yet one could
also add the observation that “death is different” in a few additional
important ways. First, the death penalty has enormous visibility and
salience both within the United States as a symbol of crime policy and
in the broader world as a symbol of American lack of respect for an

190

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

emerging world consensus on universal human rights. Second, the
death penalty is a tiny part of American crime policy, even in the
states that use it the most. Compare the current rate of about 50 executions per year nationwide to the national incarceration rate of
about 2.3 million people. Any constitutional regulation of capital
punishment thus will be both highly visible and relatively insignificant
in its effect on national or state crime policy. Whether intentional or
not, the Supreme Court’s capital jurisprudence offers a means to legitimate American penal policy by ameliorating some of its harshest
aspects and portraying the Court as a counter-majoritarian scrutinizer
of state penal policy, while leaving the fundamental pillars of America’s true penal exceptionalism intact. The United States’s claim to
the title of the world’s leading incarcerator remains untouched by
the constitutional regulation of capital punishment, yet such regulation gets a disproportionate degree of attention because of the power
of the death penalty as a symbol in numerous different arenas.
As a result, constitutional regulation of capital punishment both
obscures and normalizes the excesses of American penal policy. The
problems of mass incarceration, racial disparities in punishment, and
the failed drug war are obscured because they inevitably fall into the
shadows when the spotlights of national and world attention are focused by the Supreme Court on highly dramatic issues regarding
American death penalty practices. Moreover, extremely lengthy sentences are normalized by capital litigation: successful capital litigants,
after all, are almost always “rewarded” with sentences of life without
possibility of parole. Even the lengthiest sentences lose their horror
when they are so avidly sought and so victoriously celebrated by the
(rarely) successful capital litigant. In these ways, the success of capital
litigants under the Eighth Amendment offers little comfort to and
indeed likely limits the chances of successful challenges by noncapital litigants.
B. Constitutional Regulation of Defense Counsel
The regulation of the effectiveness of defense counsel under the
Sixth Amendment presents some of the same potential dangers as
Eighth Amendment proportionality regulation, but in a contrasting
manner. While the Supreme Court developed two distinct lines of
doctrine under the Eighth Amendment for capital and non-capital
litigants, the Court has always insisted that there is but a single standard for attorney competence under the Sixth Amendment. In recent years, however, the Court has applied this unitary standard in a
much more demanding manner to capital defense counsel during

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

191

sentencing proceedings. There is perhaps stronger reason in the
Sixth Amendment context to think that this more demanding approach in capital cases may redound to the benefit of all criminal defendants, but the distinct possibility remains that the Court’s disparate treatment of capital and non-capital cases will work to legitimate
the patently inadequate criminal defense services that are all too often provided in ordinary criminal cases.
The very case in which the Supreme Court first announced its
current constitutional standard for the regulation of defense counsel
made clear that the Court was unlikely to forge two separate stan117
dards for capital and non-capital cases. Strickland v. Washington was
a capital case in which the defendant had confessed and pleaded
guilty (against the advice of counsel) to three capital murder charges.
The Supreme Court case involved Washington’s later challenge on
federal habeas corpus review, with new counsel, to the minimal sentencing presentation by his trial counsel to the sentencing court.
This challenge presented something of a mixed bag. On the one
hand, Washington’s defense counsel—perhaps from a sense of self118
confessed “hopeless[ness]” —failed to do much of anything to pre119
pare for his client’s capital sentencing hearing. On the other hand,
the vigorous investigation later performed by habeas counsel suggested that there wasn’t a great deal of helpful information that
120
could have been unearthed on Washington’s behalf.
The Court
concluded that neither prong of its newly minted test for establishing
ineffective assistance of counsel had been met: counsel’s investigation and presentation had not been shown to be constitutionally “un-

117
118
119

120

466 U.S. 668 (1984).
Id. at 699.
Counsel spoke to the defendant’s mother and wife on the phone, but never met with
them in person, nor contacted any other possible character witnesses, nor sought any independent psychological or psychiatric evaluation of his client, nor requested that the
state conduct a presentence investigation. Rather, counsel relied on Washington’s acceptance of responsibility for his crimes, his apparent lack of a criminal history (which a presentence investigation would likely have rebutted), and his self-described state of “extreme mental or emotional disturbance” (one of Florida’s statutory mitigating
circumstances). Id. at 672–74.
There were more than a dozen friends, neighbors, and relatives who would have provided
favorable character evidence. This good character evidence, however, was undercut by
Washington’s damning admissions to other criminal activity that had not been revealed
during his initial sentencing proceeding, but would have been used to rebut the testimony of the character witnesses. Moreover, the psychological and psychiatric reports solicited by habeas counsel concluded that Washington was not under the influence of extreme emotional disturbance at the time of crimes, though he was “chronically frustrated
and depressed because of his economic dilemma.” Id. at 675–77.

192

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

reasonable,” nor had Washington been shown to have been “prejudiced” by his counsel’s alleged failings in the sense that there was no
reasonable probability that the outcome of the sentencing would
121
have been different but for his attorney’s failures.
Washington’s case clarified that capital sentencings and ordinary
criminal trials alike are subject to the same overarching two-prong
standard for assessing the constitutional adequacy of counsel. Moreover, the case signaled very clearly that the bar was being set intentionally high for the invalidation of criminal convictions (or capital
sentences) on the ground of inadequate counsel. The Court was remarkably candid about its fear of opening the floodgates of litigation
and the unfairness of evaluating attorney decision-making with the
122
benefit of hindsight. Thus, the Court refused to create any “checklist” of specific minimum requirements for adequate representation
and exhorted lower courts to accord a “strong presumption” of ade123
quacy of representation and to give deference to attorney strategy.
Even the fairly general ABA Guidelines for the provision of defense
services were not strongly endorsed by the Court; rather, they were to
be treated as guides—“but . . . only guides”—for assessing the reason124
ableness of defense attorney choices in individual cases.
Thus, from the very beginning, Strickland appeared to be an equalopportunity obstacle to constitutional claims of inadequate counsel.
Neither capital defendants nor ordinary criminal defendants were
able to meet the very high showing required by the new test. One
early application of Strickland by the Supreme Court in a capital case
demonstrated quite clearly how demanding the new standard was
125
proving to be. In Burger v. Kemp, the petitioner’s capital defense
counsel presented no mitigating case whatsoever at his sentencing
hearing, which resulted in a death sentence. Indeed, counsel performed virtually no investigation in preparation for the sentencing
hearing. Counsel had met with Burger for a total of only about six
hours in preparation for both the guilt and the sentencing phase of
his trial, and relied on his client to suggest possible witnesses or mitigating evidence by asking whether Burger could produce evidence of
126
“anything good about him.”
Unsurprisingly, this question did not

121
122
123
124
125
126

Id. at 698–700.
Id. at 689–90.
Id. at 688–89.
Id. at 688.
483 U.S. 776 (1987).
Id. at 813 (Blackmun, J., dissenting).

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

193

elicit the information later compiled by habeas counsel of a what the
127
district court called the petitioner’s “tragic childhood” —a childhood marked by family turmoil, physical abuse, neglect, and psychological problems. Although the Supreme Court concluded that trial
counsel “could well have made a more thorough investigation than
128
he did,” the Court ultimately concluded that counsel’s limited in129
vestigation could be viewed as a reasonable “strategic decision” in130
fluenced by “the defendant’s own statements or actions,” which had
failed to alert counsel to the value of pursuing further mitigating evidence. Burger sent an unmistakable signal to lower courts about the
deference they were to accord the choices of trial counsel, even in
capital cases, when life was on the line. As a result, Strickland claims,
though ubiquitous and often reflecting egregiously poor lawyering,
were virtually certain losers—a fact well recognized by lawyers and
131
documented in reviews of both capital and non-capital litigation.
Against this backdrop, it was startling when the Supreme Court
invalidated on Strickland grounds three separate capital sentences
from three different states over a period of slightly more than five
years (from 2000 to 2005). Even more surprising was the fact that
each of the three decisions reversed state court decisions despite the
newly deferential standard of review imposed by the Antiterrorism
132
and Effective Death Penalty Act of 1996 (“AEDPA”).
The three
cases, read together, represent a sea change in the approach of the
Supreme Court to the application of Strickland—at least in capital
sentencing proceedings. Whether all criminal defendants should
take heart from this new scrutiny is, of course, another question.
133
The first of the three cases, Williams v. Taylor, was the first Supreme Court case to interpret the new standard of review under
AEDPA. Despite the Court’s conclusion that Congress did indeed
require greater deference to the legal analysis of state courts, the

127
128
129
130
131

132
133

Id. at 794 (quoting Burger v. Kemp, 753 F.2d 930, 937–38 n.7 (11th Cir. 1985)).
Id.
Id. at 795.
Id. (quoting Strickland v. Washington, 466 U.S. 668, 691 (1984)).
See, e.g., Stephen B. Bright, Counsel for the Poor: The Death Sentence Not for the Worst Crime but
for the Worst Lawyer, 103 YALE L. J. 1835, 1857–66 (1994) (illustrating how inadequate capital defense services were tolerated under Strickland); William S. Geimer, A Decade of Strickland’s Tin Horn: Doctrinal and Practical Undermining of the Right to Counsel, 4 WM. & MARY
BILL RTS. J. 91, 97–161 (1995) (illustrating Strickland’s failings in the wider run of criminal
cases).
Pub. L. No. 104-132, 110 Stat. 1214, 1217–26 (codified in scattered sections of 28 U.S.C.).
See infra text accompanying notes 149–66 for a more detailed discussion of AEDPA.
529 U.S. 362 (2000).

194

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

Court nonetheless rejected the conclusion of the Virginia Supreme
Court that Williams had received effective assistance of counsel at his
capital sentencing proceeding. The scope of the decision in Williams
was limited in that it dealt only with the “prejudice” prong of the
Strickland test. The state habeas trial court had found that Williams’
counsel had been ineffective at his sentencing hearing, and the Virginia Supreme Court assumed, without deciding, that trial counsel’s
performance had indeed been deficient. The only question before
the U.S. Supreme Court was whether to affirm the Virginia Supreme
Court’s conclusion that Williams had not been prejudiced by his lawyer’s incompetence. Thus, Williams was the exceedingly rare case in
which the state and federal courts agreed that Strickland’s strong presumption of competent lawyering had been overcome. This agreement had a sound foundation: Williams’ trial lawyer failed to uncover dramatic evidence of his client’s extreme mistreatment, abuse,
and neglect as a child, testimony that his client was borderline mentally retarded and might have organic mental impairments, and powerful testimony from the state’s own experts that Williams might not
134
pose a danger in the future if incarcerated rather than executed.
As for the sentencing presentation, the Supreme Court acerbically
noted that the bulk of defense counsel’s closing “was devoted to explaining that it was difficult to find a reason why the jury should spare
135
Williams’ life.”
The Supreme Court rejected the Virginia Supreme Court’s analysis of the “prejudice” prong on three grounds, one of which was peculiar to the case, two of which were generalizable to other capital defendants, but none of which had much relevance to the application
of Strickland to ordinary criminal defendants. The ground peculiar to
the case was the Virginia Supreme Court’s strange characterization of
the Strickland prejudice prong as somehow based on more than
“mere” outcome determination—an analysis that led the Supreme
Court to the highly unusual conclusion that, even under AEDPA deference, the state court’s conclusion could not be upheld because it
136
had simply applied the wrong legal standard. The two more generalizable grounds were first, that the state court had failed to consider
the totality of the mitigating evidence in the case (from both the trial
and the later habeas proceeding), and second, that the state court
had failed to give appropriate weight to the mitigating evidence un134

Id. at 370.

135

Id. at 369.

136

Id. at 397.

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

195

covered by habeas counsel by stressing the issue of future dangerous137
ness to the exclusion of moral culpability.
The first of these two more generalizable grounds might offer
some modest assistance to non-capital defendants in that it suggests
that various pieces of evidence that a trial lawyer erroneously fails to
investigate and present must be considered in their totality. But it is
rarer outside the context of capital sentencing that a lawyer’s investigative failures will be concentrated around a single issue (such as
mitigation). Thus, the aggregation principle for which Williams
might plausibly stand offers substantially less assistance outside of the
special context of investigation of mitigation. Moreover, and much
more powerfully, only in the capital context are defendants routinely
appointed lawyers in state and federal habeas proceedings. Because
the inadequacy of trial counsel’s investigation can be demonstrated
only by a more complete investigation by habeas counsel (consider
the presentations in Strickland, Burger, and Williams), the Court’s willingness to carefully consider the impact of such later investigations
necessarily privileges the capital litigant over the non-capital litigant.
The second of the two generalizable grounds is simply inapposite
to non-capital litigation. The Supreme Court’s insistence that the
state court consider the relevance of mitigating evidence to the jury’s
assessment of the defendant’s moral culpability (and not merely his
future dangerousness) reflects the distinctive nature of the decision
at issue in capital sentencing—the appropriateness of death as punishment. In ordinary criminal trials, evidence that trial counsel fails
to uncover and present on behalf of a client is assessed only against
the government’s case for conviction, along the unitary dimension of
“guilty” versus “not guilty.” Capital cases have a more qualitative and
inescapably moral dimension—even assuming that the defendant is
guilty and eligible for capital punishment, is the defendant someone
who ought to be put to death? The considerations that inform this
decision are different from the factual determinations that trial juries
are called upon to make in ordinary criminal trials, and the Supreme
Court’s admonition in Williams offers nothing that will impact determinations of “prejudice” in ordinary criminal cases.
138
In the second of the three startling reversals, Wiggins v. Smith,
the Court went much further than it had in Williams by addressing directly Strickland’s first prong, in particular, the requirements for reasonable investigation. As in all of the previous capital sentencing
137
138

Id. at 397–98.
539 U.S. 510 (2003).

196

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

challenges under Strickland, Wiggins’s habeas counsel uncovered evidence of a “bleak” life history—including “evidence of severe physical
and sexual abuse petitioner suffered at the hands of his mother and
139
while in the care of a series of foster parents.”
In contrast to Williams (and also Strickland and Burger), however, Wiggins was represented at trial by two experienced and apparently able public defenders, who devoted substantial time and thought to his defense,
eventually committing themselves to a strategy of “residual doubt” at
sentencing—arguing that even if Wiggins participated in some way in
felony murder of the elderly victim, he was not the actual killer. Although trial counsel uncovered some evidence of Wiggins’s limited
intellectual capacities and difficult life, they failed to uncover the
dramatic evidence eventually compiled in the “social history” commissioned by habeas counsel. The Supreme Court concluded that
this failure constituted deficient lawyering under the Sixth Amendment and that the Maryland courts’ conclusion to the contrary was
not merely wrong, but unreasonably so.
Some of the bases for the Court’s conclusions in Wiggins have
more potential (not yet realized) to be broadly generalizable than the
Court’s analysis in Williams. First, in stark contrast to Burger, the
Court rejected the state’s (and the dissent’s) attempt to portray counsel’s failure to present evidence of Wiggins’s life history as “strategy.”
Rather, the Court concluded that “counsel chose to abandon their
investigation at an unreasonable juncture, making a fully informed
140
decision with respect to sentencing strategy impossible.” This holding breaks no new doctrinal ground, as Strickland itself insisted that a
reviewing court must consider the reasonableness of the investigation
141
that underlies any strategic decision. But Wiggins reflects a new willingness on the part of the Court to apply this requirement with some
vigor. Whether this vigor will extend outside of the capital context
has yet to be tested in the Supreme Court. Second, the Court noted
that it was “standard practice” in Maryland to prepare a social history
of the defendant in capital cases, a practice also endorsed by the ABA
Guidelines for the Appointment and Performance of Counsel in
142
Death Penalty Cases. Once again, the Court took pains to note that
it was merely applying Strickland rather than revising it, but the shift
from Strickland’s reference to ABA standards as “only guides” to Wig-

139
140
141
142

Id. at 516.
Id. at 527–28.
See id. (citing Strickland v. Washington, 466 U.S. 668, 690–91 (1984)).
Id. at 524.

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

197

gins’s repeated reference to and quotation from the ABA’s death
penalty Guidelines represents another unexpected shift in emphasis.
This shift toward incorporation of ABA standards as the foundation
of constitutional reasonableness—if extended outside of the capital
context—could redound to the benefit of all criminal defendants, as
the ABA has been considerably more “checklist” oriented in its consideration of counsel’s duties than have the vast majority of courts
143
applying Strickland.
On the other hand, the Wiggins Court’s consideration of the
“prejudice” prong of the Strickland test, like the analysis of the Williams Court, relied on a distinctive feature of capital sentencing.
While the Williams analysis relied on the distinctively moral nature of
the substantive decision that capital juries are called upon to make,
the Wiggins Court relied on a distinctive procedural feature of Maryland’s capital sentencing process—the fact that a single vote for life
would not “hang” a jury, but rather would require the imposition of a
life sentence. The Supreme Court explained, “Had the jury been
able to place petitioner’s excruciating life history on the mitigating
side of the scale, there is a reasonable probability that at least one juror
144
would have struck a different balance.”
It is hard to see how this
analysis offers any applicability to determinations of prejudice from
inadequate trial presentations.
145
The Court’s third capital sentencing reversal, Rompilla v. Beard,
was the most fact-specific and the least generalizable to any other
context, capital or non-capital. Rompilla’s lawyers had, like all of the
others, failed to uncover a substantial amount of mitigating evidence—in this case, evidence of a neglected childhood, serious alcoholism within the family and on the part of Rompilla himself, and indications of Rompilla’s serious mental illness and cognitive
impairment. Rompilla’s lawyers, like those of Wiggins, were experienced, dedicated counsel who did a fair amount of investigation on
his behalf, none of which had turned up this mitigating evidence.
The Court held that Rompilla’s lawyers made one quite specific error—they failed to look at a file, available as a public court record, on
which the prosecution had given notice that it intended to rely at sentencing to prove a prior offense, similar to the one for which Rom-

143

144
145

The Court cited the ABA standards not only in Wiggins, but also in Williams, 529 U.S. 362,
396 (2000), and Rompilla v. Beard, 545 U.S. 374, 387 & nn.6–7 (2005), a trifecta for the
new relevance of ABA guidance—at least in death cases.
Wiggins, 539 U.S. at 537 (emphasis added).
545 U.S. 374 (2005).

198

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

pilla faced capital sentencing. It turned out that this file contained
prison files with leads to all of the mitigating evidence that Rompilla’s
lawyers had missed.
The very specific nature of the error described by the Court—the
importance of the prior conviction to the government’s sentencing
presentation, the amount of notice that defense counsel was given of
the prosecution’s intent to rely upon the court file, the ease with
which defense counsel could have accessed the file, and the trove of
relevant information that the file turned out to possess—renders it
very difficult to identify any doctrinal proposition advanced by the
case. Moreover, the case was decided by a 5-4 margin, with Justice
O’Connor as the decisive vote in the majority. Justice O’Connor retired only a few months later, and her seat on the Court was taken by
Justice Alito, who had authored the Third Circuit opinion reversed by
the Court in Rompilla. This switch in personnel makes it even harder
to say what Rompilla stands for—if anything.
The combined effect of Williams, Wiggins, and Rompilla has been
to hearten advocates of greater constitutional regulation of defense
146
counsel by the courts. As the above discussion suggests, it is possible that these cases reflect (or may engender) a greater commitment
to applying the Strickland test in a more demanding manner not only
in capital sentencing proceedings, but also in ordinary criminal cases.
More skeptical scrutiny by courts of lawyers’ post-hoc claims of “strategy” (which are ubiquitous) and more consultation of expert assessments of counsel’s basic duties (such as those provided by the ABA)
would clearly improve, albeit modestly, the capacity of courts to regulate defense counsel under the Constitution. But it is at least equally
possible that the three cases reflect a special inflection of Strickland
relevant only to the distinctive (and very small) context of capital sentencing. The simple fact that the Court chose to review only cases involving challenges to representation in capital sentencing proceedings, as well as the emphasis in the Court’s analyses on special
substantive and procedural aspects of such proceedings, suggests that
the Court may be signaling (or may be interpreted by lower courts as

146

See, e.g., John H. Blume & Stacey D. Neumann, “It’s Like Deja Vu All Over Again”: Williams
v. Taylor, Wiggins v. Smith, Rompilla v. Beard and a (Partial) Return to the Guidelines Approach to the Effective Assistance of Counsel, 34 AM. J. CRIM. L. 127, 129 (2007) (stating that
these three cases “have provided some reason for optimism”); David Cole, Gideon v.
Wainwright and Strickland v. Washington: Broken Promises, in CRIMINAL PROCEDURE
STORIES 101, 125 (Carol S. Steiker ed., 2006) (stating that these three cases constitute
“rays of hope”).

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

199

signaling) a greater willingness to scrutinize defense representation
only in this limited context.
Should this more limited view of the Williams, Wiggins, and Rompilla trilogy trouble or dishearten the non-capital criminal defense
bar? On the one hand, one could take the “camel’s nose” view and
posit that capital defendants represent the “thin edge of the wedge”
that will eventually shift the intensity of the scrutiny (from less to
more) that courts accord the adequacy of defense counsel services in
all cases. On the other hand, as this Article argues more generally,
there is a risk that special treatment of capital cases is premised on its
inapplicability to the much larger and much more potentially destabilizing mass of ordinary criminal defendants. Moreover, there is the
further, more troubling possibility that the special attention paid to
the representation of capital litigants will obscure or even work to legitimate the general system of indigent defense representation. As
noted above, the failures of capital trial lawyers are generally brought
to light only when new counsel are appointed during state or federal
post-conviction proceedings, and these new counsel perform the investigation that trial counsel failed to do. Two features of the world
of ordinary criminal cases work against the possibility of real scrutiny
of defense counsel preparation and investigation. First, as noted
above, only capital defendants are routinely appointed counsel in
post-conviction proceedings. Thus, despite the very real possibility
that ordinary criminal defense counsel will fail to investigate adequately, there is little chance that any inadequacy will be brought to
light for the vast majority of criminal defendants who cannot afford
to privately fund post-conviction counsel. Greater doctrinal insistence
on scrutiny of defense counsel services will do little in the absence of
some mechanism to bring inadequate representation to the attention
of courts.
Second, unlike most capital defendants, the vast majority of ordinary criminal defendants plead guilty, often on the basis of advice offered after inadequate preparation and investigation by their lawyers.
Exactly how often, however, is anyone’s guess because the adequacy
of the preparation, investigation, and advice offered to defendants
who plead guilty routinely escapes judicial review. This is not because
Strickland doesn’t apply in the guilty plea context. Rather, defendants
who plead guilty and later seek to overturn their convictions on the
grounds of inadequate representation must demonstrate “prejudice”
in the form of a reasonable probability that they would not have pled

200

[Vol. 11:1

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW
147

guilty but rather would have insisted on going to trial. Merely showing that adequate preparation or investigation would have allowed
defense counsel to strike a better deal is insufficient. Given the often
vast differential between the sanctions that defendants risk if they go
148
to trial and the plea bargains that they are offered, it will be extraordinarily difficult to demonstrate in any particular case that a defendant would not have pled guilty at all.
These structural impediments to any substantial judicial review of
the adequacy of defense counsel preparation and investigation in the
vast majority of ordinary criminal cases mean that doctrinal shifts in
the intensity of scrutiny under the Strickland standard will be largely
meaningless, even if they extend more broadly outside of the capital
context. But the appearance of tough scrutiny, especially by the Supreme Court, may well create the false impression, especially to the
uninitiated, that our criminal justice system is far more intensively
regulated than it really is. This real possibility of legitimization can
increase the resistance to the necessary legislative action that will always lie at the heart of any real reform of the way that indigent defense services are delivered.
C. Federal Habeas Corpus Review
The constitutional doctrines regarding proportional punishment
and effective assistance of counsel both privilege capital litigants over
non-capital litigants—the first formally through the creation of two
separate lines of doctrine, and the second informally through differential application of the same doctrinal framework. In the preceding
two sections, we explored the possibility that the “differentness” of
death cases might necessarily exclude greater doctrinal scrutiny in
non-capital cases, and indeed might even work to obscure or legitimate troubling practices in ordinary criminal cases. We concede that
our concerns have yet to be confirmed empirically; moreover, our
suspicions are by their nature difficult to verify or measure, even if
completely accurate. In contrast to the necessarily speculative and
slippery possibilities that we chart above, the recent revolution in the
structure of federal habeas corpus review presents a different set of
issues regarding the way that capital cases may affect the administration of the broader criminal justice system.

147
148

See Hill v. Lockhart, 474 U.S. 52, 60 (1985) (White, J., concurring in judgment).
See generally John H. Langbein, Torture and Plea Bargaining, 46 U. CHI. L. REV. 3 (1978)
(criticizing vast sentencing differentials between trials and plea bargains).

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

201

In the habeas context, rather than receiving especially solicitous
constitutional treatment to the exclusion of ordinary criminal cases,
capital cases became the archetype that ushered in new procedural
barriers to constitutional relief for all criminal defendants. Moreover, in this context, there is no need to speculate about the effect
that capital cases have had on criminal law and procedure; rather, the
149
results are plainly written in the provisions of AEDPA. The AEDPA
experience draws our attention to the darker shadows that inevitably
accompany the bright light that capital cases shine on the criminal
justice system. Just as wrongful convictions and inadequate counsel
seem that much more compelling in the capital context and can draw
media attention and law reform efforts that ordinary criminal cases
cannot, the pathologies of capital litigation—especially the extraordinary lengths of time that often elapse between conviction and execution—draw more than their share of attention as well. The reform
of federal habeas review is an example of how the window-opening
potential of capital litigation can lead to the building of insurmountable walls in the form of formidable procedural impediments to constitutional relief.
The scope and availability of federal habeas corpus review of state
criminal convictions became a persistent issue, both for the federal
judiciary and for Congress, in the second half of the twentieth century in the wake of the Supreme Court’s incorporation through the
Fourteenth Amendment of almost all of the criminal provisions of
the Bill of Rights. With new and often imprecisely defined constitutional rights in state criminal proceedings, state prisoners flooded the
federal courts with petitions for habeas relief from unconstitutional
confinement. For decades, Congress considered (and sometimes
150
passed) legislation refining the scope and availability of the writ,
and the Supreme Court continually reconsidered its approach to key
151
questions regarding the effect of state procedural defaults, the ret152
roactivity of federal habeas judgments, and the preconditions for
149
150
151

152

Antiterrorism and Effective Death Penalty Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-132, 110 Stat.
1214, 1217–26 (codified in scattered sections of 28 U.S.C.).
See Wright v. West, 505 U.S. 277, 305 (1992) (O’Connor, J., concurring) (chronicling several decades of proposed legislation to amend the federal habeas statute).
Compare Fay v. Noia, 372 U.S. 391 (1963) (holding that state procedural defaults foreclose
federal habeas review only if the defendant deliberately bypassed state procedures), with
Wainwright v. Sykes, 433 U.S. 72 (1977) (holding that state procedural defaults foreclose
federal habeas review unless the defendant can show cause and prejudice).
Compare Linkletter v. Walker, 381 U.S. 618 (1965) (holding that the retroactive application of new constitutional rules in federal habeas cases depends on a consideration of
various factors on a case-by-case basis), with Teague v. Lane, 489 U.S. 288, 311 (1989)

202

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

153

holding federal evidentiary hearings.
Finally, in response to the
Oklahoma City bombings and concerns that those responsible would
not be executed in a timely fashion, Congress acted to alter the structure of federal habeas so as to ensure an “effective death penalty”—
the “EDP” in the AEDPA statute. AEDPA represents the most recent
and radical rewriting of the federal habeas statute—a reworking that
has substantially inhibited the ability of the federal courts to enforce
the federal constitutional rights of both capital and non-capital petitioners.
AEDPA’s most radical departure is, of course, the new standard of
review, codified in 28 U.S.C. § 2254(d), forbidding the granting of
the writ unless the state court proceedings resulted in a decision that
was “contrary to, or involved an unreasonable application of, clearly
154
established Federal law.” By a narrow margin, the Supreme Court
155
concluded in Williams v. Taylor that the statutory language did indeed require a profound change from the previously accepted de
novo standard of review. Two recent death cases reveal just how
powerful the deference required by AEDPA can be. In Brown v.
156
Payton, Justice Breyer cast the crucial fifth vote for reversing the
Ninth Circuit’s grant of habeas relief to Payton on his capital sentencing claim. Justice Breyer wrote separately to explain that he would
have voted the other way on the Eighth Amendment merits, but that
his resolution of the case was altered by AEDPA-required deference:
“In my view, this is a case in which Congress’ instruction to defer to
the reasonable conclusions of state court judges makes a critical dif157
ference.”
In a truly outrageous case of just a few months ago, Buntion v.
158
Quarterman, a Texas trial court judge admitted to stating in open
court that he believed he was “doing God’s work to see that the de-

153

154
155
156
157
158

(holding that new constitutional rules apply retroactively in federal habeas cases only
when they prohibit certain primary conduct or adopt procedures “implicit in the concept
of ordered liberty”).
Compare Townsend v. Sain, 372 U.S. 293 (1963) (listing six circumstances in which a federal evidentiary hearing is mandatory), with Keeney v. Tamayo-Reyes, 504 U.S. 1 (1992)
(authorizing a federal evidentiary hearing only when a defendant can show cause and
prejudice or a “fundamental miscarriage of justice” would result if the hearing were disallowed).
28 U.S.C. § 2254(d) (2006).
529 U.S. 362, 403–05 (2000).
544 U.S. 133 (2005).
Id. at 148 (Breyer, J., concurring) (citing 28 U.S.C. § 2254(d)(1)).
524 F.3d 664 (5th Cir. 2008).

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL
159

203

fendant Buntion gets executed,” among numerous other indications of his lack of impartiality in the high-profile capital case before
him. The federal district court judge who heard Buntion’s petition
for a writ of habeas corpus granted him relief on his claim of judicial
bias, but the Fifth Circuit reversed. Describing the AEDPA standard
160
of review as “highly deferential,” the Fifth Circuit explained that
while the judge’s statements were “very troubling and hardly reflec161
tive of the high standards that judges should strive to maintain,” so
much so that they resulted in a public reprimand from the Texas
162
State Commission on Judicial Conduct, there was still no room under AEDPA for upholding a grant of federal habeas relief.
Obviously, the new deferential standard will pose similar hurdles
for non-capital and capital defendants alike. But some of the other
provisions of AEDPA will prove to be even more onerous for noncapital petitioners—rather ironically, since Congress’s stated intent
was to ensure a more “effective death penalty.” In particular,
AEDPA’s one-year statute of limitations, its absolute ban on sameclaim second petitions, its higher bar for filing new-claim second petitions, its onerous exhaustion provisions, and its restrictions on federal evidentiary hearings pose hurdles that are much more difficult to
clear for petitioners without appointed counsel. Because there is no
constitutional right to appointed counsel in habeas proceedings, and
because only capital defendants are routinely provided counsel in
state and federal post-conviction proceedings, it is the ordinary
criminal defendant (the vast majority of whom are indigent) who is
most impeded by AEDPA’s tighter requirements.
One might counter this argument (that non-capital defendants
have been harmed, perhaps disproportionately, by the restructuring
of federal habeas motivated by the perceived excesses of capital litigation) by noting that non-capital defendants did not have much to
lose, habeas-wise, in the first place. This was Stephen Bright’s point
during the live symposium that spawned this paper: he observed that
the typical non-capital defendant seeking habeas relief has no effective access to the courts without the help of appointed counsel, rendering the right to habeas review essentially meaningless. “I might as
well fly a Boeing 747 by myself,” he quipped. This is a fair point, finding some support in a pre-AEDPA reported rate of federal habeas re-

159
160
161
162

Id. at 667 (quotation marks omitted).
Id. at 675.
Id. at 676.
Id.

204

JOURNAL OF CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

[Vol. 11:1

lief of only 1 in every 100 non-capital cases. However, a recent study
of the effects of AEDPA found that post-AEDPA, the rate dropped
163
from 1 in 100 to 1 out of every 341 cases filed. One could say that
either one of these rates is vanishingly small (Bright’s point). But
another crucial fact to note is the absolute number of non-capital habeas petitions filed on a yearly basis—a number greater than
164
18,000. Even a very low rate of success still represents a substantial
number of cases, and undoubtedly some rather egregious ones (if the
reported facts of the Buntion case are any indication). So there is still
some modest regulation of state court excesses going on in federal
habeas review, and AEDPA’s more than three-fold reduction should
count as a real loss.
III. CONCLUSION
Having challenged the comforting “window opening” story that
death penalty advocacy and litigation promotes the interests of all
criminal defendants, and having explored the darker story of the
“wall building” potential of particular capital punishment strategies
and doctrines, what is to be done? Our purpose here is not to propose a solution to the conflicts that we chart. We do not necessarily
think that an “innocence” strategy or LWOP laws are always wrongheaded, no matter what the context. Nor do we mean to suggest that
the Supreme Court’s “death is different” doctrinal edifice should be
dismantled. After all, it is entirely reasonable to believe that death is,
in fact, different. Rather, we seek to draw attention to the unrecognized limitations and tensions that death penalty strategies and doctrines generate for the much larger population of ordinary criminal
defendants. To recognize that “death is different” is also to assert
that incarceration (as opposed to death) is different, too—less severe,
less final, less problematic, and less worthy of attention. In light of
our current crisis of mass incarceration, we need to be wary of any
such implication.
To be wary, however, requires being aware. Once the potential
conflicts between the interests of capital and non-capital defendants
are recognized, it then becomes possible to try to gauge their severity
and to structure advocacy and litigation strategies so as to avoid or
163

164

See NANCY J. KING ET AL., NAT’L CTR. FOR STATE COURTS, HABEAS LITIGATION IN U.S.
DISTRICT COURTS: AN EMPIRICAL STUDY OF HABEAS CORPUS CASES FILED BY STATE
PRISONERS UNDER THE ANTITERRORISM AND EFFECTIVE DEATH PENALTY ACT OF 1996, at 52,
58 (2007), http://www.ncsconline.org/D_Research/publications.html#F.
Id. at 9–10.

Dec. 2008]

OPENING A WINDOW OR BUILDING A WALL

205

minimize such conflicts. Sometimes, a conflict might be so severe as
to suggest that a death penalty reform (say, the passage of an LWOP
bill) might, under the circumstances, be so likely to have such large
negative effects on non-capital defendants as not to be “worth it.” In
such circumstances, even genuinely useful reforms may be worth forgoing or actively opposing (even unsuccessfully). Whether to reject
(and work to defeat) potentially harmful or legitimating reforms or
whether to work around them depends on the relative weights of
165
harm, legitimization, and reform, as we have suggested elsewhere.
Such weighing needs to be done, but it can be only if the community
of capital and criminal defense lawyers—small and beleaguered as it
already is—honestly confronts the issues that could potentially divide
them. We are thus doubly inspired to offer the above reflections—as
scholars in pursuit of “truth,” of course, but also as reformers in pursuit of the best possible improvements to our criminal justice system
as a whole.

165

See Carol S. Steiker & Jordan M. Steiker, Should Abolitionists Support Legislative “Reform” of
the Death Penalty?, 63 OHIO ST. L.J. 417, 424 (2002).

 

 

The Habeas Citebook Ineffective Counsel Side
Advertise Here 4th Ad
PLN Subscribe Now Ad