Skip navigation
The Habeas Citebook: Prosecutorial Misconduct - Header

Iowa Law Review by the Light of Virtue Prison Rape Sigler M 2006

Download original document:
Brief thumbnail
This text is machine-read, and may contain errors. Check the original document to verify accuracy.
SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

By the Light of Virtue:∗
Prison Rape and the Corruption of
Character
Mary Sigler∗∗

I. INTRODUCTION .......................................................................................563
II. THE PROBLEM OF PRISON RAPE ..............................................................568
A. MALE POPULATIONS..........................................................................571
B. RAPE ................................................................................................572
C. INMATE-ON-INMATE ..........................................................................578
D. FOCUSING ON RAPE AMONG MALE INMATES .......................................580
III. JUSTIFICATIONS FOR PUNISHMENT ..........................................................581
A. THE TRADITIONAL JUSTIFICATIONS ....................................................582
B. ALTERNATIVE EXPLANATIONS ............................................................586
IV. EIGHTH AMENDMENT JURISPRUDENCE ...................................................588

∗

The phrase “by the light of virtue” alludes to Milton:
Vertue could see to do what vertue would/By her own radiant light, though Sun
and Moon/Were in the flat sea sunk . . . /He that has light within his own cleer
brest/May sit i’ th’ centre and enjoy bright day,/But he that hides a dark soul, and
foul thoughts/Benighted walks under the mid-day Sun;/Himself is his own
dungeon.

JOHN MILTON, COMUS: A MASK PRESENTED AT LUDLOW CASTLE 1634, available at
http://www.dartmouth.edu/~milton/reading_room/comus/index.shtml (last visited Oct. 25,
2005).
∗∗ Associate Professor, Arizona State University College of Law; J.D., University of
Pennsylvania (2000); Ph.D., Arizona State University (2003). I owe special thanks to Jeffrie
Murphy and Richard Dagger for numerous discussions about these and related (and unrelated)
issues over the years. I am also indebted to Nicholas Wolterstorff and the participants in the
Erasmus Institute Summer Seminar (2004), especially Benjamin Lipscomb, who helped me to
see the virtues of virtue ethics. I am grateful as well to the participants in the Arizona Moral and
Political Theory Conference (2005), especially Jim Nickel and Mark Timmons. Finally, thanks
to Adam Spease and the editors of the Iowa Law Review for their thoughtful and careful work.

561

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

562

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

V. RIGHTS, VIRTUE, AND CHARACTER .........................................................592
A. THE RIGHTS MODEL .........................................................................593
B. VIRTUE ETHICS .................................................................................595
C. PERSONAL VIRTUE AND NATIONAL CHARACTER ..................................597
D. PUNISHMENT AND NATIONAL CHARACTER .........................................600
VI. CONCLUSION ..........................................................................................605

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

563

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

“The degree to which a society is civilized can be judged by entering its prisons.”
FYODOR DOSTOEVSKY, THE HOUSE OF THE DEAD (1860).1
“We must not exaggerate the distance between ‘us,’ the lawful ones, the respectable
ones, and the prison and jail population; for such exaggeration will make it too easy
for us to deny that population the rudiments of humane consideration.”
Chief Judge Richard Posner, Johnson v. Phelan (1995).2
I.

INTRODUCTION

During a press conference in 2001 regarding former Enron Chairman
Kenneth Lay, California Attorney General Bill Lockyer joked that he would
“love to personally escort Lay to an eight-by-ten cell that he could share with
a tattooed dude who says, ‘Hi, my name is Spike, honey.’”3 In other words,
the chief law enforcement officer of the most populous state in the country
not only acknowledges, but celebrates, rape as a feature of criminal
punishment. Meanwhile, a recent advertising campaign for a popular soft
drink featured the company’s pitch man, the comedian Godfrey,
distributing cans of soda in a prison. When he drops a can, he starts to bend
over to pick it up, but quickly stops himself, saying, “I’m not picking that
up.”4 The commercial ends with Godfrey seated in a cell next to a large,
tattooed inmate whose arm is draped around him.5 When Godfrey delivers
the company’s tag line—“When you drink 7UP, everyone is your friend”—
the inmate tightens his hold, to Godfrey’s obvious discomfort.6 Although
Lockyer’s remarks are disturbing because they were uttered by a public
official, the soda commercial may be even more unsettling, for it is based on
the market-tested assumption that prison rape is an appropriate subject of
humor and that the joke will not be lost on viewers.7
Why are prison rape jokes considered socially acceptable? Do we
believe, with Bill Lockyer, that rape is a fitting punishment for a variety of
crimes? Or does the humor mask our uneasiness about the fate of prison

1. FYODOR DOSTOEVSKY, THE HOUSE OF THE DEAD 56 (David McDuff trans., Penguin
Books 1985) (1860).
2. Johnson v. Phelan, 69 F.3d 144, 152 (7th Cir. 1995) (Posner, C.J., dissenting).
3. Investigating Enron, WALL ST. J., Nov. 30, 2001, at A14.
4. Rhonda Bodfield Bloom, Invisible Assault, ARIZ. DAILY STAR, Jan. 25, 2004, at E1
(emphasis added).
5. Doug Young, Blasted for Jail Rape Jokes, REUTERS, May 30, 2002, available at
http://www.curenational.org/new/index.html (follow hyperlink “issues”; then follow “Prison
Rape” hyperlink).
6. Id.
7. The 7UP commercial ran for two months before the parent company of 7UP,
Cadbury-Schweppes, canceled the ad in response to protests from prisoners’ rights
organizations. Id. A spokeswoman for the company noted that the commercial was well-received
by test audiences, which raised no objections to the content of the ad. Id.; see also Bodfield
Bloom, supra note 4, at E1 (describing the content of the 7UP commercial).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

564

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

inmates? Perhaps—what seems most likely—few people have thought deeply
about the treatment of prisoners because, as Judge Posner suggests, they are
not “us.”8
This Article examines the problem of prison rape in the United States
from a philosophical perspective. Of particular concern is the disparity
between our official conception of prison as a form of punishment—
punitive primarily because of the curtailment of liberty—and the deplorable
conditions characteristic of contemporary prisons. In the context of prison
rape, the Supreme Court has held that inmate-on-inmate violence may
constitute an Eighth Amendment violation only under very limited
circumstances, in effect denying relief in all but the most egregious cases.9
Yet subjecting individuals to an environment teeming with violent sexual
predators and virtually no means of self-defense would strike most people as
paradigmatically “cruel and unusual.”
The problem of prison rape, however, represents more than a failure of
prevailing constitutional doctrine; it is first and foremost a failure of our
moral obligation to treat people humanely. This claim is far from obvious, so
accustomed have we become to defining our moral obligations primarily in
terms of the positive legal rights of others. But even a more expansive
conception of individual rights, one that incorporates moral as well as legal
considerations, does not adequately capture the wrongness of prison rape.
In this context, talk of rights—the coin of the liberal realm—is both
practically and conceptually inadequate.10 A full account of the problem of
prison rape must also include an assessment of character—of the ways in
which what we do (or fail to do) defines who we are.

8. Johnson v. Phelan, 69 F.3d 144, 152 (7th Cir. 1995) (Posner, C.J., dissenting).
9. See infra Part IV. See generally, e.g., Farmer v. Brennan, 511 U.S. 825 (1994). In addition
to the Eighth Amendment, prisoners are legally protected from human rights abuses by
provisions of federal statutory law and international law. HUMAN RIGHTS WATCH, NO ESCAPE:
MALE RAPE IN U.S. PRISONS, pt. III (2001), available at http://www.hrw.org/reports/2001/
prison/report.html [hereinafter NO ESCAPE] (noting statutory provisions that allow the
Department of Justice to prosecute officials for prisoner abuse and applicable provisions of
international law). However, the primary means of redress for victims of prison abuse is private
civil litigation pursuant to the Eighth Amendment and 42 U.S.C. § 1983 (2000), which provides
a cause of action for the enforcement of constitutional rights. See id. In addition, pre-trial
detainees, who are not formally subject to “punishment” and thus not covered by the Eighth
Amendment, enjoy equivalent protection under the Due Process Clause of the Fifth
Amendment. See generally Bell v. Wolfish, 441 U.S. 520 (1979).
10. Cf. MARY ANN GLENDON, RIGHTS TALK: THE IMPOVERISHMENT OF POLITICAL DISCOURSE
110 (1991) (noting “that something is missing from the underlying assumptions of public
discourse, as well as from its basic vocabulary, in many situations where people have difficulty
translating an important concern into political or legal language”). Michael Sandel makes a
similar point in the context of the genetic engineering controversy: “In liberal societies they
reach first for the language of autonomy, fairness, and individual rights. But this part of our
moral vocabulary is ill equipped to address the hardest questions posed by genetic
engineering.” Michael J. Sandel, The Case Against Perfection, ATLANTIC MONTHLY, Apr. 2004, at
51.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

565

Before turning to these issues, the first task is to examine the nature
and scope of the problem of prison rape in the United States. Have popular
media portrayals of prison life, such as The Shawshank Redemption and HBO’s
Oz, exaggerated the problem? In Part II, a review of the empirical literature
establishes that while reliable data concerning prison rape is hard to come
by, even conservative estimates suggest a problem of considerable
magnitude. Moreover, this literature provides the basis for some
generalizations about the distinctive character of rape in the prison
environment. For example, inmate-on-inmate rape is a phenomenon
primarily limited to males.11
While the empirical evidence justifies the particular focus on male-onmale abuse in the prison environment, the focus on rape perpetrated by other
inmates also stands in need of justification. I shall argue that this facet of the
larger problem of the treatment of prison inmates raises distinctive legal and
philosophical issues that uniquely test the limitations of the traditional
liberal framework. To the extent that the analysis yields constructive insights,
they are likely to apply with equal or greater force to other forms of abuse,
especially abuse inflicted on inmates by guards and other officials.
Part III considers prison rape in the context of the traditional
justifications for punishment. Not surprisingly, this analysis reveals that
prison rape is not readily defensible in either retributive or utilitarian terms.
From the retributive perspective, the controlling value in determinations of
punishment is the infliction of suffering in proportion to an offender’s
moral desert.12 While this may initially suggest that rape would be a fitting
punishment at least for rapists, retributivists are bound to reject this crude
proportionality as inconsistent with the principle of respect for persons that
retributivism presupposes.13
Deterrence, a utilitarian rationale, might be thought compatible with
rape as a punishment for rape—or any other crime—if it were shown to be
effective in reducing the likelihood of future attacks on the innocent. But
this positive consequence would have to be weighed against the staggering
disutility of subjecting individuals to this form of treatment. Moreover, the
inherent brutality of rape might quickly expose the limits of our willingness
to countenance such utilitarian calculations in any event. After all, we are
not inclined to adopt draconian forms of punishment despite the intuitively
plausible possibility that they might be effective. So, for example, we do not
sever the hands of shoplifters, presumably because we are unwilling to
purchase crime prevention at so high a human cost.
11. See Preface to NO ESCAPE, supra note 9; see also infra Part II.A (explaining the prevalence
of male-against-male rape).
12. JEFFRIE G. MURPHY, Introduction to PUNISHMENT AND REHABILITATION 2 (Jeffrie G.
Murphy ed., 1995) (defining retributivism: a “criminal, having done wrong in the past, deserves
to suffer punishment in direct proportion to the wrong the criminal has done”).
13. Jeremy Waldron, Lex Talionis, 34 ARIZ. L. REV. 25, 48 (1992).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

566

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

The problem of prison rape, however, concerns not the formal
sentences meted out by courts, for no court officially sentences an offender
to a term of rape. Rather, inmate-on-inmate rape claims implicate the duty
of guards and officials to protect inmates from one another. Part IV reviews
the Supreme Court’s Eighth Amendment jurisprudence as it bears on the
duty of corrections officials to provide for the health and safety of their
charges. With respect to inmate-on-inmate rape, the Court has adopted the
“deliberate indifference” standard, which requires an inmate to prove that
officials disregarded a known and substantial risk of serious harm to the
inmate.14 In most cases, inmates are unable to meet this demanding burden.
In view of the limitations of prevailing constitutional doctrine, Part V is
an attempt to develop an approach to the problem of prison rape that is
independent of the Eighth Amendment. In particular, I argue that the
traditional liberal reliance on individual rights does not by itself adequately
address the problem—the wrongness—of prison rape. First, the practice of
incarceration itself reflects the determination that offenders forfeit at least
some of their rights—liberty, for example—as a result of their wrongdoing.
So it at least remains open to question whether the bundle of rights they
retain is sufficiently robust to rule out harsh, even violent, forms of
treatment. Moreover, as a practical matter, prison inmates are perhaps the
least sympathetic rights claimants in our society; they are no one’s
constituency and are typically drawn from the least influential social groups.
Under these circumstances, the exclusive focus on individual rights is
unlikely by itself to yield a strong commitment to the humane treatment of
prisoners.
Finally, the treatment of prisoners, as Dostoevsky observed, determines
in part who we are; it is a measure of our humanity. In Jesus’s formulation,
nations are to be judged by their treatment of the “least of these”15—the
most despised members among us. On this view, our response to the
problem of prison rape implicates the character of our society, reflecting
either (or both) the virtues we purport to live by or the vices that actually
animate our practices. Are we humane and compassionate? Or callous and
cruel? What guidance, if any, might a concern for virtue supply?
At first blush, questions about virtue may seem quaint in our liberal
democratic society. In a political and social environment that prizes
pluralism and diversity, talk of virtue seems somehow misplaced—more
appropriate for private religious instruction or personal self-reflection. The
recent reaction to the Abu Ghraib16 prison abuse scandal suggests otherwise,
14. See Farmer, 511 U.S. at 837; see also infra Part IV (defining the “deliberate indifference”
standard).
15. Matthew 25:40.
16. Abu Ghraib is a prison in Iraq that came under the control of coalition forces after the
invasion and occupation of Iraq in 2003. In 2004, reports surfaced alleging that prisoners had
been abused and tortured by American forces at Abu Ghraib. The story and photos of the abuse

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

567

however. For in addition to the outcry over the apparent rights violations
depicted in the photographs, we were told that the conduct did (or did not)
accurately reflect our values; that the offending soldiers were (or were not)
us.17 In this context, at least, we seemed to care deeply about our national
character.
This preoccupation with character is the distinguishing attribute of
virtue ethics. In contrast to the dominant approaches to normative ethics in
Western philosophy, which focus on either duties or consequences,18 virtue
ethics concerns the dispositions of character that human beings ought to
cultivate and possess. Thus, the rights theorist evaluates the institution of
punishment and its discrete applications primarily in terms of whether the
practices respect or violate individual rights. The consequentialist’s goal is
that the imposition of punishment maximize good consequences and
minimize bad ones. For the virtue ethicist, the aim is to impose punishment
in the appropriate way; the justness of punishment depends on the motives
for punishing and the attitude with which it is imposed.
Although virtue ethics is distinguished by the centrality of virtue and
character in determinations of right conduct, neither deontological nor
consequentialist theories reject such considerations altogether. Indeed,
Kant, perhaps the quintessential deontologist, devoted the second part of
The Metaphysics of Morals to The Doctrine of Virtue, which addresses the ethical,
as distinct from the juridical, duties of persons.19 Moreover, even
came to public attention with the appearance of an article in The New Yorker by Seymour
Hersch. See generally Seymour M. Hersch, Torture at Abu Ghraib, THE NEW YORKER, May 10, 2004.
17. See, e.g., Interview by Alhurra TV with President George W. Bush (May 5, 2004),
available at www.gpoaccess.gov/wcomp/v40no19.html (“This is not America.”); Susan Sontag,
Regarding the Torture of Others, N.Y. TIMES MAG., May 23, 2004, at 25 (“[T]he photographs are
us.”). See generally infra Part V.C.
18. The conventional account of the dominant ethical approaches distinguishes
deontological from consequentialist ethics. Deontological ethics is characterized by a commitment
to categorical rules that forbid or require certain forms of conduct. Rights-based theories,
including contemporary American liberalism, tend to be deontological, conceiving of rights as
side constraints, or “trumps,” that limit or enable individual action. See RONALD DWORKIN,
TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY 194 (1977). Consequentialism, the belief that actions should be
evaluated in terms of their consequences, recognizes and protects rights only to the extent that
they are determined to be instrumental in maximizing good consequences. The most
significant form of consequentialism is utilitarianism, according to which human welfare (or
well-being) is the good to be maximized. See generally JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO
THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION (J.H. Burns & HLA Hart eds., Methuen 1982)
(1789) [hereinafter BENTHAM, INTRODUCTION] (advocating “the greatest good for the greatest
number”). Despite the imprecision, for convenience I shall use “deontological” and “rightsbased” (on the one hand) and “consequentialist” and “utilitarian” (on the other) more or less
interchangeably.
19. See IMMANUEL KANT, THE DOCTRINE OF VIRTUE 84 (Mary J. Gregor trans., 1964)
(1797). The first part of The Metaphysics, The Doctrine of Law, addresses juridical duties—those
that can be coercively enforced by forces external to the person, including law and other forms
of social pressure. See generally IMMANUEL KANT, THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS (Mary J. Gregor
trans., 1996) (1797).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

568

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

consequentialist accounts of ethics may assign an instrumental value to the
virtues to the extent that the virtues are believed to be productive of good
consequences.20
By the same token, virtue and character do not tell the whole story of
the wrongness of prison rape, for the determination of the morally
appropriate treatment of prisoners depends in part on the moral status of
prisoners.21 That is, the “right” treatment of prisoners is essentially
connected to their status as human beings, and we should expect a very
different account if prisoners had the moral status of rodents or weeds.
Virtue ethics thus can add an important dimension to the discussion of
prison rape without displacing more familiar rights-based considerations. By
broadening our perspective in this way, it may be possible to see that we
should treat prisoners humanely not only out of respect for their rights, but
also out of respect for ourselves.
II. THE PROBLEM OF PRISON RAPE
In the 1994 film The Shawshank Redemption, the Tim Robbins character
(Andy), a young, fragile-looking bank executive convicted of murdering his
unfaithful wife and her lover, is victimized by a group of violent sexual
predators who force other male inmates to engage in oral and anal sex with
them.22 Although the film has a happy ending, Andy is periodically sexually
assaulted for about two years, until he befriends a guard who puts an end to
the attacks.23 Later, when a newly arrived inmate confesses to the murder of
Andy’s wife and her lover, we learn that Andy is innocent of the crime for
which he was convicted.
The Shawshank Redemption exemplifies what we might think of as the
Hollywood profile of prison rape: a naïve and unsuspecting non-violent firsttime offender brutalized and exploited by a group of vicious lifers. From the
moment he arrives on the yard, Andy’s victimization seems inevitable.
Despite the strict rules that prevail in the prison setting, inmates seem
readily able to gain access to one another, and Andy is attacked, among

20. See, e.g., JOHN STUART MILL, Utilitarianism, in ON LIBERTY AND OTHER ESSAYS 131, 154
(John Gray ed., 1991) (1859) [hereinafter MILL, ON LIBERTY] (noting that the cultivation of
veracity, for example, “is one of the most useful . . . things to which our conduct can be
instrumental,” because trust is “the principal support of . . . social well-being”). For
contemporary consequentialist accounts attempting to include a role for virtue theory, see
generally JULIA DRIVER, UNEASY VIRTUE (2001) and BRAD HOOKER, IDEAL CODE, REAL WORLD
(2000).
21. See CHRISTINE SWANTON, VIRTUE ETHICS 5 (2003) (“Virtues are, after all, dispositions
of responsiveness to items in the world, and these items have morally significant features (such
as status, value, or a good) which shape the requirements for appropriateness of response.”).
22. THE SHAWSHANK REDEMPTION (Castle Rock Entertainment 1994).
23. The guard arranges for Andy’s protection—by brutally beating and permanently
disabling one of the attackers—only after Andy uses his knowledge of banking and finance to
provide legal advice that allows the guard to shield his assets from the IRS. Id.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

569

other places, in the prison laundry and in the projection booth of the prison
auditorium.24 So far as we can tell, he never reports the attacks to prison
officials.
Although compelling as fiction, we may be skeptical about whether the
story is in any way typical of actual prison life. Indeed, though many firsttime offenders report that rape is what they most fear about prison, this
might itself be an artifact of the media and popular culture’s portrayals of
prison life.25 So the questions remain: How common is prison rape? What
are its typical characteristics?
The study of prison rape from an empirical perspective presents
uniquely daunting methodological challenges. In particular, researchers
must rely primarily on self-reports of sexual violence or third-party reports,
neither of which is likely to be wholly reliable.26 Many inmates are reluctant
to report rape out of shame, intimidation, or fear of being labeled a
“snitch.”27 Additionally, while it is often difficult to distinguish rape from
consensual sexual activity in ordinary settings,28 the problem is exacerbated
in the prison environment, where strong incentives, such as obtaining
protection and avoiding other forms of violence, for example, lead some

24. Id. Charles Fried notes the irony of the lawlessness in prison: “[T]he one institution in
which we have the almost unlimited right to control the lives of our fellow citizens and which is
intended to represent the ultimate commitment to order and personal security, is too often
deeply disorderly and ultimately insecure.” Charles Fried, Reflections on Crime and Punishment, 30
SUFFOLK U. L. REV. 681, 687 (1997).
25. See Richard S. Jones & Thomas J. Schmid, Inmates’ Conceptions of Prison Sexual Assault,
69 PRISON J. 53, 55 (1989). See generally Christine A. Saum et al., Sex in Prison: Exploring the Myths
and Realities, 75 PRISON J. 414 (1995); Bodfield Bloom, supra note 4. This concern is also
reflected in the film 25th Hour (Touchstone Pictures 2002), in which the main character asks
his friends to beat him up before he goes to prison so he will appear tough rather than
vulnerable to predatory inmates. The strategy of this fictional character reflects the reality of
the prison experience. According to one study, “one’s performance [in prison] is
everything. . . . The inmates who gave poor performances and were perceived as feminine by
other inmates were most often the victims of sexual assault.” Christopher Hensley et al.,
Characteristics of Prison Sexual Assault Targets in Male Oklahoma Correctional Facilities, 18 J. PRISON
VIOLENCE 595, 598 (2003) [hereinafter Hensley et al., Characteristics].
26. See, e.g., Saum et al., supra note 25, at 418 (identifying problems); Cindy StruckmanJohnson & David Struckman-Johnson, Sexual Coercion Reported by Women in Three Midwestern
Prisons, 39 J. SEX RES. 217, 226 (2002) [hereinafter Struckman-Johnson & Struckman-Johnson,
Sexual Coercion Reported by Women] (noting the limitations of an anonymous self-report survey
instrument, including deceptive reporting and self-selection).
27. See Helen M. Eigenberg, Rape in Male Prisons: Examining the Relationship Between
Correctional Officers’ Attitudes Toward Male Rape and Their Willingness to Respond to Acts of Rape, in
PRISON VIOLENCE IN AMERICA 145, 147 (Michael C. Braswell et al. eds., 2d ed. 1994); James E.
Robertson, A Clean Heart and an Empty Head: The Supreme Court and Sexual Terrorism in Prison, 81
N.C. L. REV. 433, 443 (2003) [hereinafter Robertson, Clean Heart].
28. See, e.g., JOSHUA DRESSLER, UNDERSTANDING CRIMINAL LAW 580–82 (2001) (discussing
the role of force and resistance requirements as aspects of determining whether sex was
consensual).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

570

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

inmates to be coerced into “consensual” sexual relationships.29 Finally, in the
absence of mandatory reporting requirements, most jurisdictions do not
compile data on the incidence of prison rape reported by inmates in
correctional institutions.30 Under these circumstances, generalizations about
the frequency of prison rape have only limited value, though even the most
skeptical analysts do not deny the existence of the problem.31
Despite this uncertainty, recent congressional findings in connection
with the Prison Rape Elimination Act of 2003 (“PREA”)32 provide some
insight into the nature and scope of the problem of prison rape in the
United States. Relying on the testimony of social scientists and penologists,
Congress “conservatively” estimated that thirteen percent of inmates in the
United States have been sexually assaulted in prison.33 Based on this figure,
Congress found that “nearly 200,000 inmates now incarcerated have been or
will be the victims of rape. The total number . . . assaulted in the past 20
years likely exceeds [one million].”34 Congress also found that young firsttime offenders and inmates with mental illness are at the greatest risk for
victimization.35 Finally, Congress noted the “severe physical and
psychological effects” associated with prison rape, including the spread of
HIV/AIDS and other sexually transmitted diseases, as well as the increased
unemployment, homelessness, and recidivism among prison rape victims
when they are released.36

29. See, e.g., NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at pt. V (“[I]n the context of imprisonment, much
more so than in the outside world, the concepts of consent and coercion are extremely
slippery.”); Saum et al., supra note 25, at 418 (“The problem is that some sexual activity may
appear consensual although an inmate may actually be coerced into participating only because
he feels that there are no other alternatives.”).
30. NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at pt. VIII (reporting that almost half of the fifty states do not
collect data on rapes occurring in their jails and prisons).
31. See, e.g., Daniel Lockwood, Sexual Exploitation in Prison, in ENCYCLOPEDIA OF AMERICAN
PRISONS 440 (Marilyn D. McShane & Frank P. Williams eds., 1996) (“[S]ocial science
researchers have found the rate of prison rape to be much lower than claimed by popular
writers on the topics, who have guessed at the rate without using proper victimization surveys.”);
Saum et al., supra note 25, at 414 (noting the disparity between popular perceptions about the
frequency of prison rape and the actual number of documented incidents).
32. 42 U.S.C. §§ 15601–09 (2000).
33. Id. § 15601. PREA defines rape as “carnal knowledge, oral sodomy, sexual assault with
an object, or sexual fondling of a person, forcibly or against that person’s will.” Id. § 15609. This
definition is generally consistent with the terminology from empirical studies of prison rape.
See, e.g., Cindy Struckman-Johnson et al., Sexual Coercion Reported by Men and Women in Prison, 33
J. SEX RES. 67, 69 (1996) [hereinafter Struckman-Johnson et al., Sexual Coercion Reported by Men]
(casting the survey in terms of nonconsensual “sexual contact,” defined as “touching of genitals,
oral, anal, or vaginal sex”). I shall use “rape” in a similarly broad way to include various forms of
sexual abuse effected by force, intimidation, or coercion.
34. 42 U.S.C. § 15601.
35. Id.
36. Id.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

571

These findings highlight some of the distinctive attributes and harms of
prison rape. The bulk of empirical research also indicates that inmate-oninmate rape is largely a problem among male prison populations.37 Beyond
this empirical evidence, rape, as distinct from other forms of abuse, and
inmate-on-inmate abuse, as opposed to abuse by prison officials, raises
distinctive legal and philosophical issues that require special inquiry. What
follows is an attempt to spell out the considerations that warrant the
particular focus on inmate-on-inmate rape among male prison populations.
A. MALE POPULATIONS
Although contemporary research establishes that inmate-on-inmate
rape is primarily a problem among male prison populations,38 the earliest
studies of sex in prison focused on consensual relationships among women
and girls in reform schools and other institutional settings.39 These findings
suggest several possible explanations for the relatively low frequency of
documented inmate-on-inmate rape among female prison populations.
First, according to these early studies, institutionalized females are
generally less violent than male inmates, often organizing themselves into
“families” whose members satisfy one another’s “psychological, social, and
physiological needs.”40 In addition, some researchers have speculated that
the relatively low rates of sexual coercion among female inmates is due to
the smaller size of women’s facilities, the less violent criminal histories of
female inmates, or possibly “women’s general disinclination to initiate
sexual coercion.”41
While the earliest studies lacked the rigor and precision of
contemporary methodologies, the results from more recent studies do not

37. See Preface to NO ESCAPE, supra note 9; infra text accompanying notes 38–45.
38. See, e.g., Preface to NO ESCAPE, supra note 9 (noting that a gender-neutral
announcement of the Human Rights Watch rape study distributed to male and female
populations alike yielded more than 200 responses from males, but none from females);
Struckman-Johnson et al., Sexual Coercion Reported by Men, supra note 33, at 67 (finding rates of
victimization for male inmates of twenty-two percent and seven percent for female inmates in a
Midwestern state prison system).
39. See Christopher Hensley et al., Introduction: The History of Prison Sex Research, 80 PRISON
J. 360, 360 (2000) [hereinafter Hensley et al., Introduction].
40. Id. at 361.
41. Struckman-Johnson & Struckman-Johnson, Sexual Coercion Reported by Women, supra
note 26, at 218. One inmate-observer, who published a qualitative analysis of her own
experiences in prison, noted that “rape occurred at a much lower rate than other forms of
sexual behavior.” Leanne Fiftal Alarid, Sexual Assault and Coercion Among Incarcerated Prisoners:
Excerpts from Prison Letters, 80 PRISON J. 391, 399 (2000). The study in Midwestern prisons
supports the conclusion that the rate of prison rape among female (and presumably male)
populations depends in part on the nature of the facility. See Struckman-Johnson & StruckmanJohnson, Sexual Coercion Reported by Women, supra note 26, at 224 (reporting substantially higher
rates of sexual coercion in the one “rough prison” of three studied, “where nearly half the
inmates had committed serious crimes against persons”).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

572

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

differ significantly from the earlier findings. Homosexual conduct among
incarcerated women is not uncommon, but there is generally little evidence
of coercion or force.42 At least part of the reason for the lack of evidence of
sexual coercion among female inmates may be the relative dearth of
contemporary studies. As one researcher notes, “until 1996 no research
existed on the topic of sexual coercion in female prisons.”43 Although one
recent study found higher-than-expected rates of victimization perpetrated
by female inmates in an unnamed Midwestern prison,44 the primary form of
significant sexual abuse for women inmates remains victimization by male
guards.45
B. RAPE
Perhaps more controversial than the focus on male victims is the
particular focus on rape as distinct from other forms of violence or abuse.
The empirical evidence indicates that rape results in greater physical and
psychological harm for victims than other forms of violence or abuse;46 that
it exacerbates interracial tensions within prisons and in the community at
large;47 and that it increases the level of violence, both inside and outside of
prison.48 Moreover, the fact that AIDS is rampant in prison—the second

42.
43.

Hensley et al., Introduction, supra note 39, at 361.
Christopher Hensley et al., Inmate-to-Inmate Sexual Coercion in a Prison for Women, 37 J.
OFFENDER REHABILITATION 77, 81 (2003) [hereinafter Hensley et al., Inmate-to-Inmate].
44. See Struckman-Johnson & Struckman-Johnson, Sexual Coercion Reported by Women, supra
note 26, at 225 (“One of our most important findings was that nearly one half of the incidents
of sexual coercion were carried out by female inmates.”).
45. See, e.g., Agnes L. Baro, Spheres of Consent: An Analysis of the Sexual Abuse and Sexual
Exploitation of Women Incarcerated in the State of Hawaii, 8 WOMEN & CRIM. JUST. 61, 62 (1997)
(citing numerous sex abuse “scandals” involving corrections officials and female inmates);
Hensley et al., Inmate-to-Inmate, supra note 43, at 85 (noting that relatively low rates of sexual
coercion among female inmates is likely due to an exclusive focus on coercion perpetrated by
inmates). The problem of officials directly abusing inmates is almost certainly more, not less,
troubling than inmate-on-inmate abuse. See, e.g., Thomas W. Pogge, How Should Human Rights Be
Conceived?, in THE PHILOSOPHY OF HUMAN RIGHTS 187, 194 (Patrick Hayden ed., 2001)
(exploring the intuition that wrongdoing by government is worse than similar “private” wrongs:
“Official moral wrongs masquerade under the name of law and justice and they are generally
committed quite openly for all to see . . . .”). However, as discussed below, the problem of
inmate-on-inmate abuse raises distinctive legal, moral, and philosophical concerns that make it
the “harder” case to address. See infra Part II.C.
46. Prison Rape Elimination Act of 2003, 42 U.S.C. § 15601 (2000) (“Victims of prison
rape suffer severe physical and psychological effects that hinder their ability to integrate into
the community and maintain stable employment upon their release from prison.”).
47. Id. (noting that the high incidence of prison rape “increases the level of interracial
tensions and strife within prisons and, upon release of perpetrators and victims, in the
community at large”).
48. Id. (noting “increases [in] levels of violence, directed at inmates and at staff, within
prisons” as well as increased risk of “violent crime by individuals . . . brutalized by prison rape”).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

573

leading cause of death after natural causes49—might be reason enough to
focus on the sexual practices that spread HIV.
Whatever the empirical evidence in the prison context, the question of
whether rape in any context is worse than other forms of physical attack
cannot be answered with confidence. Although most U.S. jurisdictions
reserve harsher penalties for rape than for other acts of battery—treating
rape as only somewhat less serious than murder50—the rationale for its
special status in the criminal law has occasionally been called into question.51
For example, in a widely cited essay challenging the assumption that rape is
worse than other forms of interpersonal attack, philosopher Michael Davis
considers and rejects several possible justifications for rape’s special status in
the criminal law.52 Davis concludes that rape should be treated the same as
“simple battery,” the unlawful touching of another person.53 Under his
modified scheme, a “typical rapist probably would not receive . . . more than
six-months imprisonment.”54 As counterintuitive as this might seem, Davis’s
thought-provoking discussion merits closer attention.
Davis argues that part of what accounts for the rape-is-worse
phenomenon is the natural tendency to associate rape with extreme
brutality and grave physical injury—the “worst rape.”55 In fact, however,
Davis cites evidence to suggest that rape does not usually involve great bodily
harm and that few victims suffer long-term psychic injury.56 More common is
what Davis calls “simple rape,” in which the victim is not physically injured.57

49. NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at pt. VI (“AIDS is currently the second leading cause of
death among prison inmates.”) (citing U.S. DEP’T OF JUSTICE, BUREAU OF STATISTICS, HIV in
Prison & Jails, 1995 (1998), http://www.ojp.usdoj.gov/bjs/pub/pdf/hivpj95.pdf).
50. Michael Davis, Setting Penalties: What Does Rape Deserve?, 3 L. & PHIL. 61, 66 (1984).
51. See, e.g., Jeffrie G. Murphy, Some Ruminations on Women, Violence, and the Criminal Law,
in IN HARM’S WAY 209, 211 (Jules Coleman & Allan Buchanan eds., 1994) [hereinafter Murphy,
Some Ruminations] (exploring the feminist impact on criminal law theory); Martin D. Schwartz
& Todd R. Clear, Toward a New Law on Rape, 26 CRIME & DELINQ. 129, 135 (1980) (proposing a
“normalization” of rape law by subsuming it under the general heading of assault).
52. Davis, supra note 50, at 81–88.
53. Id. at 61.
54. Id. at 106. Davis regards this relatively lenient punishment for rape as a worthwhile
trade-off for more certain convictions. See id. (“Punishing rape less severely might make
punishment more certain.”).
55. Id. at 97.
56. Id. at 71–72 (citing sources). But see JULIE A. ALLISON & LAWRENCE S. WRIGHTSMAN,
RAPE: THE MISUNDERSTOOD CRIME 152–61 (1993) (examining the short- and long-term effects
that many rape victims experience); Lynne Henderson, Rape and Responsibility, 11 L. & PHIL.
127, 175 (1992) (“[A]ll rape is a form of soul murder . . . .”); Emily C. Shanahan, Stranger and
Nonstranger Rape: One Crime, One Penalty, 36 AM. CRIM. L. REV. 1371, 1376–82 (1999) (outlining a
broad account of the non-physical harm of rape, including psychic trauma, loss of trust, and
fear).
57. This aspect of Davis’s argument is also controversial. See Coker v. Georgia, 433 U.S.
584, 612 (1977) (Burger, C.J., dissenting) (“To speak blandly, as the plurality does, of rape
victims who are ‘unharmed’ . . . takes too little account of the profound suffering the crime

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

574

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

Because simple rape, according to Davis, is akin to simple battery, simple
kidnapping, and other offenses against the person, the penalties for all such
offenses should be similar.
To support this conclusion, Davis identifies what he takes to be the
viable candidates for treating rape as more serious and then attempts to
show that none stands up to scrutiny. Although Davis successfully
undermines the case for some possible justifications—including Marxist,
feminist, and “traditional”58 accounts of rape law—the bulk of his analysis is
unpersuasive. The following discussion focuses on aspects of Davis’s “fearbased” and “loss-based” analyses.
Davis contends that most people, if given a choice, would prefer to be
(simply) raped rather than badly beaten. Indeed, Davis observes that men
and women “do not seem to be different when forced to choose between
suffering rape and suffering other serious crimes.”59 Both will choose rape.
Based on these results,60 Davis concludes that simple rape is a less serious
harm to an individual than other crimes and deserving of a correspondingly
less severe penalty.
Apart from the controversial claim that most people would choose rape
in these circumstances—which seems far from obvious—Davis’s conclusion
has a more serious flaw. For even if we accept Davis’s empirical premise, we
should be cautious about drawing any strong conclusions from these results.
As Jeffrie Murphy has observed, we might not want to rest too much weight

imposes upon the victims and their loved ones.”); Henderson, supra note 56, at 174–75
(rejecting Davis’s assumption that “rape is not painful, that forcible intercourse is not violent”);
Shanahan, supra note 56, at 1376 (noting that all rape victims experience “the violence and
injury of penetration itself”).
58. According to the “traditional analysis,” rape is a serious crime because it results in the
loss of a woman’s chastity. Davis, supra note 50, at 80. Davis notes that while such a concern may
help explain how we came to have the rape laws that we have, it is almost certainly obsolete. Id.
Thus, “[m]ost of us think many things dearer than chastity (for example life, limb, or health).”
Id.
59. Id. at 84.
60. Davis is candid that his claims are not based on reliable survey methods. Rather, he
conducted informal polls among colleagues and friends, and invites others to test his results by
conducting similar surveys. Id. A recent incident in Arizona casts doubt on Davis’s results.
During a hostage crisis at an Arizona prison in the spring of 2004, inmates held two guards, a
male and a female, for fifteen days. I doubt whether I was alone in having an especial fear that,
even if the hostages were eventually released, it was the female guard who faced the graver
threat (short of death). Although I was relieved when the guards were released alive, my heart
sank when it was confirmed that the female guard had been repeatedly raped. Although the
male guard’s face was badly beaten, it was the female guard’s ordeal that seemed especially
devastating. A series of newspaper stories marking the anniversary of the stand-off, the longest
in U.S. history, featured a profile of the female guard and her efforts to cope with the aftermath
of the incident. Only a brief paragraph was devoted to the male guard’s recovery, focusing on
his physical condition and professional plans. I suspect many of us regarded this asymmetry as
perfectly appropriate. See Judi Villa, “I’ve Got to Find a New Lois;” Ex-Hostage Struggles to Rebuild Her
Life, ARIZ. REPUBLIC, Jan. 16, 2005, at A23.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

575

on the relative prospective fear of these experiences.61 To illustrate, Murphy
imagines being put to the choice of having his fingernail pulled out with
pliers or having his character believably defamed and his reputation
destroyed. He thinks he would choose the latter, the extreme reputational
harm, “purely because of a physiological, reflexive response to the idea of
intense physical pain.”62 This does not establish that the actual harm of the
nail-pulling is worse; only that one is likely to anticipate the prospect with
greater fear and trepidation. This suggests that rape may indeed be more
harmful than a severe beating regardless of one’s prospective assessment in a
forced-choice situation. If so, it seems reasonable for the criminal law to
punish more severely the offense that carries the greater harm.
Davis also rejects the “objectification” argument, according to which the
special wrongness of rape consists in the fact that such an attack reflects the
use of the victim’s body—the victim’s “self”—by another “as if it were a mere
object one owned.”63 Davis counters that all crimes of interpersonal violence
treat the victim as an object, so this feature cannot justify the special status of
rape. In all such cases, “[t]he victim’s body becomes a mere inconvenience
the attacker treats in any way he thinks may serve the ends he is pursuing.”64
Moreover, taken to its logical conclusion, the objectification argument is
incoherent on this view, at least with respect to rapists motivated by a desire
to degrade their victims. After all, a mere object cannot be degraded. “If the
rapist’s victim becomes an object in his eyes as soon as the crime begins,
what then is the point of continuing the crime?”65
Several problems plague Davis’s response to the objectification
argument. First, rape is not simply the use of another’s body for one’s own
purposes; it is a particular kind of use. Contrary to Davis’s claim, the victim’s
body is not merely an “inconvenience” en route to some other end the
attacker is pursuing; it is integral to the attack. In this way, rape is unlike at
least some brutal beatings, which may be incidental to an attacker’s other
objective. Thus, for example, a beating may be motivated by the desire to
extract information, to gain access to property, or to intimidate a victim. If
these goals could be achieved without a beating, the attacker would
presumably refrain. By contrast, the victim’s body is essential to the rape, not
just by definition, but because sexually dominating the victim is the end at
which the rapist aims.66 Thus, even for a rapist using the victim’s body as a

61. Murphy, Some Ruminations, supra note 51, at 217.
62. Id.
63. Davis, supra note 50, at 79.
64. Id.
65. Id.
66. See, e.g., ALLISON & WRIGHTSMAN, supra note 56, at 54 (characterizing rape as “‘the
sexual expression of aggression, rather tha[n] the aggressive expression of sexuality’” (quoting
D. Gelman, The Mind of the Rapist, NEWSWEEK, July 23, 1990, at 47)). Allison and Wrightsman
explore the various typologies of rape, which broadly include stranger and acquaintance rape.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

576

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

means to another end—as a component of genocide,67 ethnic cleansing,68 or
political revenge,69 for example—the use of the victim’s body constitutes the
attacker’s ultimate aim; it is not merely contingently related to the attack.70
Davis’s argument that the objectification analysis is self-refuting also
fails. The rapist motivated by a desire to degrade his victim does not literally
mistake the victim for an object; rather, he treats her as an object. After all, it
is not by accident that he rapes a person and not an animal or a piece of
fruit. He rapes precisely to assert power over a human being and to literally
degrade her, that is, to reduce her value.71 Although this might be true of
some brutal beatings, it does not seem to be an essential element of such
attacks.
Finally, Davis’s rejection of the distinction between rape and ordinary
battery reflects a misapprehension of the experience of rape. My own
intuition is that the harm of rape is especially grave because it represents a
mockery—a perversion—of something that is singularly intimate, precious,
and human. As the Supreme Court has observed in a different context,
decisions about sex and sexuality “involv[e] the most intimate and personal
choices a person may make in a lifetime, choices central to personal dignity
and autonomy.”72 The rapist thwarts his victim’s autonomous choice,

Id. at 46–98. In addition, within these categories, rapists appear to have a variety of motivations.
See id. at 54–59, 68; see also id. at 74–77 (noting the significance of traditional power differentials
between men and women in the context of acquaintance rape).
67. See generally Christoph Schiessl, An Element of Genocide: Rape, Total War, and International
Law in the Twentieth Century, 4 J. GENOCIDE RES. 197 (2002).
68. Id. at 200; see also Cheryl Benard, Rape as Terror: The Case of Bosnia, 6 TERRORISM & POL.
VIOLENCE 29, 37 (1994) (relating a pregnant Bosnian victim’s story of being raped by a group
of Serbs, who told her “even in the womb, it was not too late to turn her baby into a Serb”).
69. See Schiessl, supra note 67, at 202.
70. This conception of the logical relationship between the use of the victim’s body and
the aim of the attack is modeled on Antony Duff’s conception of the expressive function of
punishment. In characterizing criminal punishment as expressive, Duff denies that the
imposition of suffering on wrongdoers is merely a means to an end:
[T]o talk thus of punishment as a reformative endeavour is not to suggest that it is
a contingently efficient means towards a further and independently identifiable
end: for the kind of reform at which punishment aims can be achieved only
through the kind of suffering which punishment aims to impose on, or induce in,
the criminal.
R.A. Duff, Expression, Penance and Reform, in PUNISHMENT AND REHABILITATION, supra note 12, at
170.
71. Not all rapists have this motivation, but Davis confines his critique of the
objectification argument to the rapist who seeks to “degrade or demonstrate power over a
victim.” Davis, supra note 50, at 79.
72. Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 851 (1992); see also Lawrence v.
Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 567 (2003) (“When [consensual] sexuality finds overt expression in
intimate conduct with another person, the conduct can be but one element in a personal bond
that is more enduring.”). The Court has also characterized rape as “the ultimate violation of
self” short of murder, expressing “almost total contempt for the personal integrity and

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

577

treating her, and perhaps himself, like a rutting animal. Although, as Davis
notes, various acts of battery similarly defy the wishes of victims, none entails,
as rape does, the corruption of an act invested with the complex meaning
and significance of human sexuality.73 Davis’s mistake is to consider the
various justifications for rape’s special status in isolation from one another,
when it is the totality of these considerations that yield the judgment that
rape is worse.
The dynamics of rape in the prison environment further complicate the
analysis of whether rape is worse than other forms of physical abuse.
Although certain aspects of rape are common in all settings—the use of
threats of violence and intimidation to compel compliance, the admixture
of violence and sexuality, and an array of complex social meanings74—
certain attributes distinguish rape in the prison setting. In particular, prison
rape is a means of domination that elevates the status of rapists at the
expense of victims within the confines of a relatively small and insular social
group.75 Moreover, having been subordinated once, prison rape victims are
marked as targets and subject to repeated victimization.76 In extreme cases,

autonomy of the female victim and for the latter’s privilege of choosing those with whom
intimate relationships are to be established.” Coker v. Georgia, 433 U.S. 584, 596 (1977); see also
id. at 612 (Burger, C.J., dissenting) (“Rape is not a mere physical attack; it is destructive of the
human personality.”).
73. Davis notes that other acts of battery—back-slapping, hugging, and kissing, for
example—can also be expressions of affection among intimates. Davis, supra note 50, at 90.
Thus, “[s]exual battery is not unique among batteries in requiring acts that are not in
themselves harmful.” Id. By the same token, according to Davis, battery can involve one’s
“private parts”—just as rape does—as, for example, a surgeon who maliciously removes an
unwilling patient’s sexual organs. Id. at 91. Finally, a perpetrator seeking sexual gratification
need not touch one’s “private parts”; he may, for example, force his sex organ into an armpit, a
navel, or an ear. Id. Nor is sexual gratification a requirement for the offense of rape. Id. But
these observations miss the point. What is distinctive about rape is the combination of factors—
debasing something distinctively invested with human significance by means of a battery on
one’s most intimate and private self. It may be a separate question whether our society should
discard that distinction, though my own view is that we would lose something that enriches our
lives were we to do so. In any case, Davis has not refuted or even addressed these considerations
that seem central to any discussion of the wrongness of rape. For arguments that rape’s special
status reflects underlying pathologies in sexual interactions, see generally Pamela Foa, What’s
Wrong with Rape?, in ETHICS IN PRACTICE: AN ANTHOLOGY 212 (Hugh LaFollette ed., 1997).
74. See generally ALLISON & WRIGHTSMAN, supra note 56.
75. See NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at pt. V (“[I]n the prison context, where power and
hierarchy are key, rape is an expression of power. It unequivocally establishes the aggressor’s
dominance, affirming his masculinity, strength, and control at the expense of the victim’s.”).
76. See id. (“Stigmatized as a ‘punk’ or ‘turn out,’ the victim of rape will almost inevitably
be the target of continuing sexual exploitation, both from the initial perpetrator and . . . from
other inmates as well.”); Struckman-Johnson et al., Sexual Coercion Reported by Men, supra note 33,
at 71 (noting the results of a study indicating that “[t]argets, on the average, had experienced
nine episodes of pressured or forced sex”).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

578

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

victims may become the “property” of another inmate to be used, traded, or
sold as a valuable commodity.77
In addition to the psychological trauma characteristic of rape victims
generally, victims of male-on-male rape also report feeling a loss of their
manhood.78 Thus, in addition to the feelings of guilt, shame, and self-doubt
that so many rape victims experience,79 male rape victims often feel
emasculated as well, believing that a “real man” would have fought more
strenuously to avoid being raped.80 Indeed, despite recent modifications in
the law of rape that reflect a more progressive attitude toward female rape
victims, such as the abolition or relaxation of force and resistance
requirements and shield laws that exclude evidence of an accuser’s sexual
history and moral character,81 male rape victims are more likely than not to
have their negative self-perceptions reinforced by others. In particular,
guards and other inmates often view male rape victims as contemptibly weak,
probably latent homosexuals who may have invited, or at least welcomed,
the sexual encounter.82
C. INMATE-ON-INMATE
The final distinction concerns the particular focus on inmate-on-inmate
rape as opposed to the direct abuse of inmates by guards and other officials.
From a legal and political perspective, cases of direct official abuse are
almost certainly more troubling. As a general matter, official malfeasance
has the capacity to harm a greater number of people.83 In addition, abuses

77. See NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at pt. V (describing incidences of inmates being enslaved,
rented, and sold).
78. See ALLISON & WRIGHTSMAN, supra note 56, at 49; NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at pt. VI
(noting the “unwritten code of inmate beliefs, that a real man ‘would die before giving up his
anal virginity’” (quoting Letter to Human Rights Watch (Oct. 13, 1996))).
79. See ALLISON & WRIGHTSMAN, supra note 56, at 154 (noting that, after fear, self-blame is
“the second most common reaction” to rape) (quoting R. Janoff-Bulman, Characterological Versus
Behavioral Self-Blame Inquiries into Depression & Blame, 37 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 1798,
1798–1809 (1979)); id. at 151 (noting the tendency of rape victims to question their worth); id.
at 166 (noting victims’ reactions of self-blame and self-doubt).
80. See NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at pt. VI (quoting a victimized inmate: “Men are supposed
to be strong enough to keep themselves from being raped.”); id. at V (noting “the common
inmate belief that a real man would never submit to rape”).
81. See ALLISON & WRIGHTSMAN, supra note 56, at 213–14.
82. See NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at pt. VI (“Unless a prisoner is visibly injured from a
sexual assault, guards often intimate that the sex was consensual: that the prisoner actually
invited it.”); James E. Robertson, The Prison Rape Elimination Act of 2003: A Primer, 10 CRIM. L.
BULL. 270, 276 (2004) (noting the tendency for prison guards to accept the “myth” that a “‘real
man’ cannot be raped because he will fight to the death”).
83. See Pogge, supra note 45, at 194. Because the state typically enjoys a monopoly on the
legitimate use of force, it has the capacity to assert its authority on a broad scale. See, e.g.,
ROBERT NOZICK, ANARCHY, STATE, AND UTOPIA 108–09 (1974) (characterizing the state in terms
of its claim to a “monopoly on the use of force”); Clifford J. Rosky, Force, Inc.: The Privatization of
Punishment, Policing, and Military Force in Liberal States, 36 CONN. L. REV. 879, 885 (2004) (making

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

579

cloaked in the trappings of legality undermine the very idea of justice under
law.84 As a result, we are more likely to regard such abuses as matters of
public concern, for we are more obviously implicated in the affirmative
abuses committed by our officials.85
Inmate-on-inmate abuse, by contrast, presents a special challenge. As an
initial matter, the ascription of responsibility to officials in such cases
represents a form of omission liability. That is, rather than assigning
responsibility on the basis of an official’s actions, we seek to assign it on the
basis of official inaction. Liability for omissions—for failures to act—is
notoriously complicated.86 In most legal contexts, individuals have no duty
to provide even minimal assistance to someone in need.87 Moreover, in both
the civil and criminal law settings, liability is ordinarily justified in terms of a
culpable mental state, which is typically based on inferences drawn from an
actor’s conduct, together with the causation of harm.88 But in the absence of
affirmative conduct, there may be nothing from which to infer a mental
state89 and no metaphysical basis for the ascription of causation.90 Indeed,
there is something quite unnatural about the formulation: “Officer Smith
caused the rape of Inmate Jones (by Inmate Doe).” In such a case, the
obvious candidate for causation (and culpability) is Inmate Doe.
In the prison context, officials do have an affirmative duty to provide for
the health and safety of inmates,91 thereby eliminating one of the most
daunting obstacles to omission liability. But even in the face of such a duty,
problems of causation and culpability persist. Thus, while the law can assign
a similar claim). In addition, the very legal mechanisms that facilitate so many aspects of our
lives can quickly grind them to a halt as well. See HLA HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 79 (2d ed.
1994).
84. See Pogge, supra note 45, at 194 (“Such [state-inflicted] wrongs do not merely deprive
their victims of the objects of their rights but attack those very rights themselves; they do not
merely subvert what is right, but the very idea of right and justice.”).
85. See id.
86. See, e.g., Joshua Dressler, Some Brief Thoughts (Mostly Negative) About “Bad Samaritan”
Laws, 40 SANTA CLARA L. REV. 971, 979 n.41 (2000) [hereinafter Dressler, Brief Thoughts]
(summarizing aspects of the debate).
87. See, e.g., Kathleen M. Ridolfi, Law, Ethics, and the Good Samaritan: Should There Be a Duty
to Rescue?, 40 SANTA CLARA L. REV. 957, 958 (2000) (noting “how little is owed by way of a duty
to rescue under Anglo-American law”). Whether one has a moral duty in such cases is less
obvious, though many of the same problems involving mental state and causation affect the
analysis of whether and when individuals have a moral duty to come to the aid of another. See,
e.g., HLA HART & A.M. HONORÉ, CAUSATION IN THE LAW 63 (1st ed. 1959); MICHAEL MOORE,
PLACING BLAME 251–329 (1997) [hereinafter MOORE, PLACING BLAME].
88. See MOORE, PLACING BLAME, supra note 87, at 403; Dressler, Brief Thoughts, supra note
86, at 982.
89. See Dressler, Brief Thoughts, supra note 86, at 982–83.
90. See MOORE, PLACING BLAME, supra note 87, at 273 (denying that “omissions cause
anything” and noting that “omissions are literally nothing at all”) (citing MICHAEL MOORE, ACT
& CRIME: THE PHILOSOPHY OF ACTION AND ITS IMPLICATIONS FOR CRIMINAL LAW (1993)).
91. See Estelle v. Gamble, 429 U.S. 97, 103 (1976); infra Part IV.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

580

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

liability by definition,92 it cannot alter the metaphysical fact that an omission
cannot cause harm.93 Moreover, even in circumstances where one has an
affirmative duty to act, the absence of an action provides, at best, a
problematic basis for an inference regarding the concomitant mental state.
That is, one’s failure to act cannot support a reliable inference about one’s
subjective mental state, which may be anything from obliviousness to
outright malice.94
These features of omission liability suggest the distinctive challenges of
assessing moral blameworthiness in the context of inmate-on-inmate rape.
Although guards and officials have an affirmative duty to protect the health
and safety of inmates, the failure to fulfill this duty lacks the obvious indicia
of liability. First, an official who fails to protect an inmate has not thereby
caused harm. Moreover, in the absence of direct abuse, or any action at all,
we can draw no reliable inferences about the official’s subjective mental
state. Finally, where the harm to an inmate is caused by another inmate,
rather than directly by a guard, we are less likely to experience the sense of
vicarious responsibility associated with the misconduct of those authorized
to act in our name.
D. FOCUSING ON RAPE AMONG MALE INMATES
As the foregoing suggests, the problem of inmate-on-inmate rape
among male prison populations is particularly troubling. First, because
inmate-on-inmate violence is a significant problem largely confined to
incarcerated males, it is in this environment that the need for reform is most
pressing. In addition, because the harm of rape generally comprises both
physical injury and extreme psychological trauma, rape represents, for
many, the ultimate violation of self short of death. Moreover, the
consequences of prison rape range from physical debilitation and personal
dysfunction to anti-social behavior and public disorder. Finally, the
complexities of omission liability render the problem of inmate-on-inmate

92. See HART & HONORÉ, supra note 87, at 65 (noting the distinction between legal
responsibility for and actual causation of harm). For example, as Hart and Honoré observe, the
law can hold an employer responsible for the acts of its employees despite the fact that the
employer did not cause the harm that resulted. Id.
93. See MOORE, PLACING BLAME, supra note 87, at 251 (observing that “absent actions
(‘omissions’) have no effects because they enter into no singular causal relations”). Moore’s
claim is not uncontroversial. See, e.g., MILL, ON LIBERTY, supra note 20, at 15 (“A person may
cause evil to others not only by his actions but by his inaction . . . .”); Dressler, Brief Thoughts,
supra note 86, at 979 n.41 (noting the “lingering metaphysical issue” regarding whether a “nonaction is ever the cause of harm”).
94. See Dressler, Brief Thoughts, supra note 86, at 982. Dressler notes that relative to our
commonplace inferences about intent based on actions, it is “far harder to determine why a
person does not act.” Id. Thus, in a hypothetical situation involving a blind person about to step
into oncoming traffic, Dressler suggests the range of possible explanations for a bystander’s
failure to act, including lack of awareness, slow reaction time, and simple fear. Id.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

581

abuse especially difficult to recognize as an urgent social problem and less
susceptible to traditional means of legal redress. Thus, without discounting
the significance of other forms of prisoner abuse, the problem of inmate-oninmate rape among male prisoners is especially intractable. Accordingly, I
shall focus on those aspects of the problem that present the greatest
challenges.
III. JUSTIFICATIONS FOR PUNISHMENT
Rape, of course, is not a formal part of any criminal sentence in the
United States.95 As a result, any analysis of rape as a justified punishment is
perhaps beside the point. But the prominent role of prison rape in the
popular imagination suggests that, despite our official rejection of punitive
rape, we may actually welcome the perceived benefits of this unavowed
feature of prison life. Thus, California Attorney General Bill Lockyer can
publicly intimate that rape would be a fitting punishment for corporate
fraud and face no significant political repercussions.96
In a 1994 survey, fifty percent of respondents said they believed that
society accepts prison rape as “part of the price criminals pay for
wrongdoing.”97 Similarly, at least some prison staff reportedly view “rape as a
legitimate deterrent to crime and a just desert for its commission.”98 Other
observers have suggested that rape is used as a “management tool,”99 a
means of maintaining “‘peace’” by “‘allowing aggressive predators to have

95. See Farmer v. Brennan, 511 U.S. 825, 833 (1994) (offering numerous cases defining
duties of prison officials and addressing prison conditions).
96. See Investigating Enron, supra note 3. In 2002, one year after suggesting that he would
welcome the rape of Enron Chairman Ken Lay in prison, Lockyer was re-elected as Attorney
General of California, and his name was mentioned as a strong gubernatorial candidate for
2006. See Greg Lucas, Names for 2006 Gubernatorial Election Includes Actor Arnold’s, SAN DIEGO
UNION-TRIB., Nov. 10, 2002, at A14 (“Lockyer was the biggest vote getter on the Democratic
ticket, the only one to crest 50 percent and capture 150,000 more votes than Gov. Gray Davis,
who bested Republican challenger Bill Simon in Tuesday’s election.”). By contrast, an eightterm Illinois Republican legislator, Cal Skinner, was defeated in a 2000 primary election after
campaigning for an end to prison rape in Illinois. Skinner attributes his defeat at least partly to
his efforts on behalf of prisoners. Eli Lehrer, Hell Behind Bars: The Crime That Dare Not Speak Its
Name, NAT’L REV. ONLINE, Feb. 5, 2001, http://www.spr.org/en/news/pre2002/02501.html. As
Skinner notes, “[c]onvicted criminals aren’t the most popular people with conservative voters
in a conservative district.” Id.; see also Fred Dickey, Rape, How Funny Is It?, L.A. TIMES MAG., Nov.
3, 2002, at 44 (quoting Skinner: “There’s no lobbyist crusading against prison rape. For a
lawmaker, it’s a mission without a political reward.”).
97. Charles M. Sennott, Poll Finds Wide Concern About Prison Rape; Most Favor Condoms for
Inmates, BOSTON GLOBE, May 17, 1994, at 22.
98. Robertson, Clean Heart, supra note 27, at 446.
99. Lehrer, supra note 96; see also Helen M. Eigenberg, Correctional Officers’ Definitions of
Rape in Male Prisons, 28 J. CRIM. JUST. 435, 436 (2000) (noting that “some officers may use rape
or the threat of sexual violence to control inmates”).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

582

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

their way.’”100 In extreme cases, prison staff have orchestrated inmate-oninmate rapes to punish rules violations101 or to enhance the punishment of
despised sex offenders.102
A review of the traditional justifications for punishment establishes that
none can accommodate rape as a form of punishment without
compromising other important values that structure the institutions of the
criminal law. But our apparent ambivalence about prison rape suggests that
we may be willing to turn a blind eye to rape in pursuit of certain punitive
goals that we are unwilling to defend openly. After considering the
traditional justifications, I will briefly consider “vengeance” and “blind-eye
deterrence” as alternative explanations for public attitudes about prison
rape.
A. THE TRADITIONAL JUSTIFICATIONS
The traditional justifications for punishment in American criminal
law fall into two broad categories: utilitarian103 and retributive.104 The
principal utilitarian justifications—incapacitation,105 deterrence,106 and

100. James E. Robertson, Compassionate Conservatism and Prison Rape: The Prison Rape
Elimination Act of 2003, 30 NEW ENG. J. ON CRIM. & CIV. CONFINEMENT 1, 9 (2004) [hereinafter
Robertson, Compassionate Conservatism] (quoting congressional testimony of Mark Earley,
President and Chief Financial Officer, Prison Fellowship Ministries).
101. See Mark Arax & Mark Gladstone, Five Guards Are Indicted in Prison-Rape Scandal,
CONTRA COSTA TIMES (Walnut Creek, Cal.), Oct. 9, 1998, at A17 (reporting that a former guard
“described how fellow officers had transferred [the victim] into the cell of [‘the Booty Bandit’],
knowing that the 6-foot-3, 230-pound prison enforcer would likely rape the small, skinny
Dillard”).
102. Bob Egelko, Former Prison Guards Sentenced, S.F. CHRON., Feb. 7, 2003, at A19
(reporting convictions of two former guards who induced inmates to rape “convicted child
molesters and rapists, as well as prisoners who would not cooperate with them”).
103. Utilitarianism is the most prominent form of consequentialism, the view that actions
should be evaluated in terms of their consequences. For the utilitarian, the consequence to be
maximized is happiness—or utility.
104. See MOORE, PLACING BLAME, supra note 87, at 92 (identifying “two sorts of prima facie
justifications of punishment—effecting a net social gain (utilitarian), and giving just deserts
(retributivist)”).
105. Incapacitation involves disabling an offender from engaging in further criminal
conduct. The most obvious forms of incapacitation are imprisonment and execution; in both
cases, offenders are physically prevented from offending again. See, e.g., JEREMY BENTHAM,
Panopticon Versus New South Wales, in 4 THE WORKS OF JEREMY BENTHAM 173, 183 (John
Browning ed., Russell & Russell, Inc. 1843) [hereinafter BENTHAM, Panopticon] (“This
contrivance [incapacitation] was as firmly laid down in school-logic as could be wished.
Mischievously or otherwise, for a body to act in a place, it must be there.”).
106. Deterrence may be either “general” or “specific.” General deterrence concerns the
“prevention of similar offenses on the part of individuals at large, viz. by the repulsive influence
exercised on the minds of bystanders by the apprehension of similar suffering in case of similar
delinquency.” Id. at 174. Specific deterrence is “prevention of similar offenses on the part of the
particular individual punished in each instance, viz. by curing him of the will to do like in the
future.” Id.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

583

rehabilitation,107—are defended in terms of the positive consequences they
are believed to bring about. In the case of deterrence, for example, its
viability as a justification for punishment is measured in terms of its efficacy
in achieving the goal of crime prevention by means of the threat of
punishment. Retributivism, by contrast, is centrally concerned with the
imposition of suffering in proportion to an offender’s moral desert.108 On
this view, punishment of the deserving is intrinsically good; its justification
does not depend on any further positive consequences that punishment
might be expected to produce. Although a retributivist will welcome the
positive consequences that punishment may incidentally yield—crime
prevention, for example, or character reformation—such consequences are
not part of the justification for punishment.109 Thus, a “retributivist punishes
because, and only because, the offender deserves it.”110
In addition to the traditional justifications in their pure forms, various
combinations of these yield further possible justifications for punishment.
Prominent among these alternatives are several versions of the expressive
theory of punishment, which draw on both utilitarian and retributive
elements.111 The expressive rationale, in general terms, views punishment as
a means for communicating a message to the offender and to society at
large—that certain behavior is unacceptable and will not be tolerated. In
this way, the expressive justification is utilitarian in character, focusing on
the forward-looking goal of expressing and affirming society’s moral
values.112 It is also retributive “in that it makes the relationship between past
crime and present punishment central to the meaning and justification of
punishment.”113

107. Rehabilitation concerns the attempt to reform a wrongdoer, either in Bentham’s
sense—by “curing” the offender of the impulse to engage in wrongdoing—or by otherwise
reforming an “offender’s character, habits, or behavior patterns so as to diminish his criminal
propensities.” ANDREW VON HIRSCH, DOING JUSTICE: THE CHOICE OF PUNISHMENTS 11 n.∗ (1st
ed. 1976).
108. See MOORE, PLACING BLAME, supra note 87, at 105.
109. See ROBERT NOZICK, PHILOSOPHICAL EXPLANATIONS 374 (1981) [hereinafter NOZICK,
PHILOSOPHICAL EXPLANATIONS] (“These further consequences are not to be dismissed simply;
but we shall see them as an especially desirable and valuable bonus, not as part of a necessary
condition for justly imposed punishment.”).
110. Michael S. Moore, The Moral Worth of Retribution, [hereinafter Moore, Moral Worth] in
PUNISHMENT AND REHABILITATION, supra note 12, at 94.
111. For variations of the expressive theory, see NOZICK, PHILOSOPHICAL EXPLANATIONS,
supra note 109, at 370; JEAN HAMPTON, The Retributive Idea, in FORGIVENESS AND MERCY 111, 130
(1988); Duff, supra note 70, at 169, 170; Joel Feinberg, The Expressive Function of Punishment, in
DOING & DESERVING 95 (1970).
112. See NOZICK, PHILOSOPHICAL EXPLANATIONS, supra note 109, at 371 (characterizing
those who view punishment primarily in terms of the goal of reforming offenders as
“teleological retributivists”); Duff, supra note 70, at 170.
113. Duff, supra note 70, at 170; see also NOZICK, PHILOSOPHICAL EXPLANATIONS, supra note
109, at 370 (“Retributive punishment is an act of communicative behavior.”); HAMPTON, supra

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

584

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

From the utilitarian perspective, punishment is justified in terms of its
effectiveness in preventing crime, while at the same time generating the
least possible amount of human suffering.114 The utilitarian principle of
deterrence115 thus defines proportionality in terms of the relevant utilitarian
goals, prescribing exactly that amount of punishment necessary to achieve
those goals; any suffering above that amount is excessive and unjustifiable.
On this view, rape might be an appropriate punishment for any crime,
provided it is enough, but no more than necessary, to reduce the likelihood
of future offenses. By the same token, a strongly worded letter of reprimand
might also suffice as a punishment for the rapist, so long as it proved
effective in achieving the goal of deterrence.
Although rape—or an angry letter—could in principle be justified as an
appropriate punishment for rape in utilitarian terms, we have good reasons
for believing that a utilitarian calculation will not yield this result for either
form of sanction. In the case of the letter, it seems highly improbable that
the threat of receiving even a very nasty letter would be sufficient to deter a
would-be rapist. We can easily imagine that, from the point of view of a
would-be rapist, the prospect of the “utility” of committing rape dramatically
exceeds the threatened disutility of receiving an angry letter.
Rape as punishment is likely to be disutilitarian as well. The positive
consequence of crime prevention would have to be weighed against the
profound disutility of imposing this form of treatment. Any such calculation
must include not only the unhappy consequences associated with the
offender’s experience of the sanction, but also the negative consequences
for those assigned to authorize, inflict, and oversee it. Among other
considerations, Kant’s (consequentialist) concern was that the imposition of
such punishments would brutalize and corrupt our own humanity as well as
that of the offenders, fostering sadism and cruelty among those who
administer criminal punishment and society in general.116 Moreover, the
very idea of state-sanctioned rape is so anathema that we would almost
certainly reject it as unacceptably barbaric.

note 111, at 130 (“So even in a situation where neither the wrongdoer nor society will either
listen to or believe the message . . . the retributivist will insist on the infliction of punishment
insofar as it is a way of ‘striking a blow for morality’. . . .”).
114. See BENTHAM, INTRODUCTION, supra note 18, at 158 (“[A]ll punishment is mischief: all
punishment in itself is evil. Upon the principle of utility, if it ought at all to be admitted, it
ought only to be admitted in as far as it promises to exclude some greater evil.”).
115. Deterrence here refers broadly to crime prevention and rehabilitation. See BENTHAM,
Panopticon, supra note 105, at 174 (defining specific deterrence in terms of the “prevention of
similar offenses on the part of the particular individual punished in each instance, viz. by curing
him of the will to do like in the future”).
116. See IMMANUEL KANT, THE METAPHYSICAL ELEMENTS OF JUSTICE *363 (John Ladd trans.,
Bobbs-Merrill Co. 1965) (1780) [hereinafter KANT, METAPHYSICAL ELEMENTS]; Waldron, supra
note 13, at 38.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

585

The retributive justification for punishment traces its modern origins to
Immanuel Kant. In Kant’s classic formulation: “The law concerning
punishment is a categorical imperative, and woe to him who rummages
around in the winding paths of a theory of happiness looking for some
advantage to be gained by releasing the criminal from punishment or by
reducing the amount of it . . . .”117 In specifying the nature and amount of
punishment that is deserved, Kant invoked the principle of lex talionis—the
“principle of equality (illustrated by the pointer on the scales of justice), that
is, the principle of not treating one side more favorably than the other.”118
Thus, “the act of punishment [should] be the same as the act that
constituted the offense.”119 Although lex talionis is not definitive of
retributivism, it provides at least some guidance in determining the
proportionate punishment in particular cases. Thus, Kant is adamant that if
an offender has committed murder, “he must die.”120 For, “[t]here is no
sameness of kind between death and remaining alive even under the most
miserable conditions, and consequently there is also no equality between the
crime and the retribution unless the criminal is judicially condemned and
put to death.”121
In the context of rape and other forms of torture, however, even Kant
rejects the easy symmetry that might otherwise warrant raping the rapist or
torturing the torturer. According to Kant, the punishment of offenders
“must be kept free of any maltreatment that would make an abomination of
the humanity residing in the person suffering it.”122 To be sure, Kant does
not provide any further defense of the claim that executing a murderer
respects the murderer’s humanity in a way that raping the rapist does not.
But we surely grasp the intuitive force of the distinction. We can readily
conceive of a “dignified death” as well as more and less humane forms of
execution. By contrast, it makes no sense to speak of “dignified rape” or
“humane torture.” These latter acts, by their very nature, degrade the
humanity of the sufferer. Accordingly, even an “arch-talon”123 such as Kant
does not countenance rape as a form of punishment, even for rapists.

117. KANT, METAPHYSICAL ELEMENTS, supra note 116, at *331.
118. Id. at *332.
119. Waldron, supra note 13, at 32. Although Kant’s conception of retributivism includes lex
talionis, many do not. See, e.g., Moore, Moral Worth, supra note 110, at 95 (“It is quite possible to
be a retributivist and to be against both the death penalty and lex talionis, the idea that crimes
should be punished by like acts being done to the criminal.”). Likewise, one committed to lex
talionis need not be a retributivist. See, e.g., Waldron, supra note 13, at 31 (“[R]easoning along
the lines of [lex talionis] might have a part to play in the determination of an appropriate
penalty even for a utilitarian judge or legislator.”).
120. KANT, METAPHYSICAL ELEMENTS, supra note 116, at *333.
121. Id.
122. Id.
123. Waldron, supra note 13, at 40.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

586

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

Finally, the expressive justification is also inconsistent with rape as a
form of punishment. First, because the expressive justification combines
retributive and utilitarian considerations, the same objections generated by
the pure theories hold as well against “expressive rape.” In addition, the
expressive justification presupposes a moral agent who is capable of
apprehending and accepting correct moral values.124 In this way, the aim is
(at least partly) to persuade an offender “not merely to obey the law, but to
accept its justified demands and judgments.”125 Thus, even if the fear of brutal
treatment were effective in bringing about obedience, the result would
reflect manipulation rather than respect for the offender’s humanity.
Moreover, the chances of achieving even manipulated obedience are
probably quite low. To the extent that rape-as-punishment is left to the
random forces of prison dynamics, the message to the offender is likely to be
systematically miscommunicated. That is, while the most vulnerable inmates
tend to be the least brutal and dangerous themselves, they will receive the
harshest “expression” of society’s values. Meanwhile, the message likely to be
received by the most violent and predatory offenders is that they can
continue to prey on the weak. Finally, even if the state were to impose rape
purposefully and systematically, it seems even less likely that offenders would
embrace the values of such a community—one that willfully subjects its
members to such brutal and degrading treatment.
B. ALTERNATIVE EXPLANATIONS
Although rape is a poor candidate for justified punishment, at least two
possible alternatives may account for its lingering appeal. One possible
explanation is simple revenge.126 That is, beyond (and perhaps behind) the

124. Duff, supra note 70, at 195.
125. Id. at 173; see also Herbert Morris, A Paternalistic Theory of Punishment, in PUNISHMENT
AND REHABILITATION, supra note 12, at 154, 158 (arguing that the moral good of punishment is
“an autonomous individual freely attached to that which is good”).
126. Revenge, strictly speaking, is the act or desire of seeking retaliation against another
who has harmed or wronged one. In this sense, revenge is personal between the victim and
wrongdoer. See NOZICK, PHILOSOPHICAL EXPLANATIONS, supra note 109, at 367 (noting that the
personal tie may extend to families and groups). For present purposes, I shall use “revenge”
more colloquially, referring generally to the desire to impose, or to see imposed, harsh
treatment on wrongdoers. In this sense, revenge may be thought of as a kind of unreflective
retributivism—a misguided perception about what offenders truly deserve; it may also reflect
more generally a “feeling of hatred—call it revenge, resentment, or what you will—which the
contemplation of such [wrongful] conduct excites in healthily constituted minds.” JAMES
FITZJAMES STEPHEN, LIBERTY, EQUALITY, FRATERNITY 152 (1967). This general meaning of
revenge is commonplace in judicial opinions. See, e.g., Schiro v. Indiana, 533 N.E.2d 1201 (Ind.
1989), cert denied, 493 U.S. 910, 914 (1989) (Stevens, J., dissenting from denial of certiorari)
(noting a jury’s role, in appropriate cases, of expressing an “outraged community’s desire for
revenge or retribution”); Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 305 (1972) (Brennan, J.,
concurring) (claiming that society has rejected punishment as a means to “get even” with
criminals); id. at 344 (Marshall, J., concurring) (noting the “demand for vengeance on the part

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

587

retributive ideal—that offenders should suffer in proportion to their moral
desert—lies the impulse for revenge.127 On this view, the moral foundation
of the criminal law is the collection of vengeful emotions that are triggered
by injury or harm, manifesting themselves in a desire to “get even.”128 In the
context of prison rape, the desire for revenge can account for the attitudes
of those guards and inmates (and others) who view sexual offenders as
worthy targets for rape. In this way, raping the rapist is a form of lex talionis—
with no Kantian side-constraints—that satisfies the visceral desire to get
even.
Another possible explanation for public attitudes toward prison rape is
a kind of blind-eye deterrence. That is, despite our unwillingness to openly
endorse the use of such tactics, perhaps we welcome what we perceive to be
the deterrent effects of the threat of prison rape. On this account, “the
tougher, colder, and more cruel and inhuman a place is, the less chance a
person will return.”129 Thus, while officially committed to the humane
treatment of prisoners, we still reap the crime control benefits of
exceptionally harsh treatment. In this way, we are not forced to confront the
tension between our principles and practices.
Regardless of whether vengeance or blind-eye deterrence provides an
accurate psychological description of public attitudes toward prison rape,
neither constitutes a justification of prison rape. Vengeance, whether meted
out by guards or other inmates, is by definition lawless.130 Similarly, blind-eye

of many persons in a community against one who is convicted of a particularly offensive act”);
Johnson v. Phelan, 69 F.3d 144, 152 (7th Cir. 1995) (Posner, C.J., dissenting) (lamenting that
the treatment of criminal offenders too often depends on “what a vengeful populace and a
resource-starved penal system choose to give them”).
127. Robert Nozick has identified five basic attributes that distinguish retribution from
revenge: (1) retribution is inflicted for a wrong, not merely a harm or injury; (2) retribution sets
an internal limit on the amount of punishment that is in proportion to the degree of the
wrong, while revenge is limitless in principle; (3) revenge, but not retribution, is personal
between the punisher and the punished; (4) revenge, but not retribution, involves “pleasure in
the suffering of another;” and (5) retribution is a general principle that calls for application
across similar cases, while revenge may (or may not) be imposed at the whim of the revenger.
NOZICK, PHILOSOPHICAL EXPLANATIONS, supra note 109, at 363–68. Despite this conceptual
distinction, Nozick acknowledges that the difference may be less stark in practice. Id. at 368. In
addition, many of those who defend retributivism as a justification for punishment recognize
that the retributive and vengeful emotions may spring from a common source. See, e.g., Moore,
Moral Worth, supra note 110, at 105; Jeffrie G. Murphy, Getting Even: The Role of The Victim, in
PUNISHMENT & REHABILITATION, supra note 12, at 151 n.32 (“Perhaps such attempts at drawing
a sharp distinction between the two have been misdirected.”).
128. JEFFRIE G. MURPHY, GETTING EVEN: FORGIVENESS AND ITS LIMITS 3 (2003).
129. Robertson, Clean Heart, supra note 27, at 446 (quoting an inmate).
130. See NOZICK, PHILOSOPHICAL EXPLANATIONS, supra note 109, at 366–68 (exploring the
necessary definitional distinction between retribution and revenge and observing that inherent
limitations on retribution are absent for revenge). Even Jeff Murphy, who offers a qualified
defense of the role of revenge in criminal punishment, suggests that such a role is only
defensible if revenge can be institutionalized. MURPHY, supra note 128, at 17–26. Thus, invoking

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

588

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

deterrence requires the willful violation of official rules and norms, and
collective self-deception about the dissonance between our principles and
practices. Whatever our psychological inclinations, such a disingenuous
subterfuge cannot be reconciled with our commitment to the rule of law.
IV. EIGHTH AMENDMENT JURISPRUDENCE
Apart from the law’s official rejection of rape or the risk of rape as a
form of punishment in the United States, several aspects of contemporary
Eighth Amendment131 jurisprudence seem conducive to challenges by
inmates seeking relief from attacks perpetrated by other inmates. As an
initial matter, the prohibition on “cruel and unusual” punishment
represents an “abstract moral principle”132 that is to be interpreted
according to “the evolving standards of decency that mark the progress of a
maturing society.”133 In light of this standard, the Supreme Court has taken a
firm rhetorical stand against rape as a form of punishment: “Being violently
assaulted in prison is simply not ‘part of the penalty that criminal offenders
pay for their offenses against society.’”134 Thus, “prison conditions may be
restrictive and even harsh, but gratuitously allowing the beating or rape of
one prisoner by another serves no legitimate penological objective, any
more than it squares with the evolving standards of decency.”135
The Court has also held that prison officials have an affirmative duty of
care toward inmates housed in their facilities. Thus, in requiring the
provision of reasonable medical care for inmates, the Court noted the
common law rule that “‘it is but just that the public be required to care for
the prisoner, who cannot by reason of the deprivation of his liberty, care for
himself.’”136 Pursuing a similar line of reasoning, the Court has made clear
that officials have a duty to protect inmates from one another: “Having
incarcerated ‘persons [with] demonstrated proclivit[ies] for anti-social,
criminal, and often violent conduct,’ having stripped them of virtually every
means of self-protection and foreclosed their access to outside aid, the

the myth of the Furies, and their transformation into the Eumenides (“kindly ones”), Murphy
observes that “they will represent not vigilante activity (with which revenge should not be
confused) but the pursuit of revenge under the constraints of law.” Id. at 20.
131. The Eighth Amendment provides: “Excessive bail shall not be required, nor excessive
fines imposed, nor cruel and unusual punishments inflicted.” U.S. CONST. amend. VIII.
132. ANTONIN SCALIA, A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION 145 (1997).
133. Trop v. Dulles, 356 U.S. 86, 101 (1958).
134. Farmer v. Brennan, 511 U.S. 825, 834 (1994) (quoting Rhodes v. Chapman, 452 U.S.
337, 347 (1981)).
135. Id. at 833 (internal citations and quotations omitted).
136. Estelle v. Gamble, 429 U.S. 97, 104 (1976) (“We therefore conclude that deliberate
indifference to serious medical needs of prisoners constitutes the ‘unnecessary and wanton
infliction of pain’ proscribed by the Eighth Amendment.” (quoting Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S.
153, 173 (1976))).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

589

government and its officials are not free to let the state of nature take its
course.”137
Despite this promising rhetoric, inmates seeking relief from abuse at
the hands of other inmates face a number of significant obstacles, the first
and most basic of which is conceptual. The constitutional basis for
challenges to the conditions of confinement is the Eighth Amendment
prohibition on cruel and unusual punishment. As the Court has noted,
however, “[t]he Eighth Amendment does not outlaw cruel and unusual
‘conditions’; it outlaws cruel and unusual ‘punishments.’”138 Accordingly, “an
official’s failure to alleviate a significant risk that he should have perceived
but did not . . . cannot under our cases be condemned as the infliction of
punishment.”139 Indeed, for at least one sitting Justice, the idea of an Eighth
Amendment challenge concerning abuse by another inmate is incoherent:
“Because the unfortunate attack [i.e., the rape] that befell petitioner was not
part of his sentence, it did not constitute ‘punishment’ under the Eighth
Amendment.”140 For Justice Clarence Thomas, the dispositive fact is that
“judges or juries—but not jailers—impose punishment.”141
Although the Court has not fully embraced Justice Thomas’s
conception of the Eighth Amendment, it has consistently circumscribed the
scope of constitutional protection for inmate-on-inmate violence. Thus,
“‘only the unnecessary and wanton infliction of pain implicates the Eighth
Amendment.’ To violate the Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause, a
prison official must have a ‘sufficiently culpable state of mind.’”142 In
particular, the Court adopted the “deliberate indifference” standard
developed in cases involving the failure to provide medical care or
treatment.143
Under the deliberate indifference standard, an official is liable for the
harm an inmate suffers at the hands of another inmate only if he consciously
disregards a known and substantial risk of serious harm to the inmate and
fails to take reasonable steps to abate the risk.144 For liability under this
subjective recklessness standard, it is not enough to show that a risk was
obvious,145 that officials should have known, or that a reasonable official

137. Farmer, 511 U.S. at 833 (internal citation omitted).
138. Id. at 837 (emphasis added).
139. Id. at 838.
140. Id. at 859 (Thomas, J., concurring).
141. Id. (internal citation omitted).
142. Farmer, 511 U.S. at 834 (quoting Wilson v. Seiter, 501 U.S. 294, 297 (1991)).
143. Estelle v. Gamble, 429 U.S. 97, 104 (1976).
144. Farmer, 511 U.S. at 830, 837.
145. The Court does note that in cases where the risk to an inmate was objectively obvious,
an official will be hard-pressed to deny that he was unaware of the risk:
Whether a prison official had the requisite knowledge of a substantial risk is a
question of fact subject to demonstration in the usual ways, including inference

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

590

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

would have known.146 An inmate must instead prove that officials did in fact
know of the danger and failed to take reasonable steps to protect him.147
In practice, the deliberate indifference standard precludes relief in all
but the most egregious cases. Among other problems, the absence in most
jurisdictions of official prison rape statistics makes it more difficult for
inmates to establish that officials were aware of and disregarded a known
and substantial risk.148 Additionally, while the surest way for an inmate to
alert officials to the existence of a risk is to report threats by other
inmates,149 the prison environment is notoriously hard on “rats,” and
inmates risk violent retaliation for snitching on other inmates.150 Finally,
inmates who risk reporting rape or threats of rape can, at best, hope to be
placed in protective custody.151 Despite the relative security that protective
custody affords, it is an unattractive option for many inmates. As one

from circumstantial evidence, and a factfinder may conclude that a prison official
knew of a substantial risk from the very fact that the risk was obvious.
See id. at 842 (internal citation omitted). In view of this, one commentator has argued that
courts should not grant summary judgment under Rule 56 to defendants in cases where
inmates have alleged facts that, if taken as true, might establish that the risk of harm was
obvious:
When a court grants summary judgment for defendant-officials in spite of an
obvious risk, it is effectively making a factual finding that the obviousness of the
risk, in the given case, does not warrant an inference of actual knowledge. It is
simply inappropriate for a court to decide this factual question on summary
judgment.
Brian Saccenti, Comment, Preventing Summary Judgment Against Inmates Who Have Been Sexually
Assaulted by Showing that the Risk Was Obvious, 59 MD. L. REV. 642, 663 (2000).
146. Farmer, 511 U.S. at 837–38.
147. Id. The Court also notes that a defendant-official’s response need not be effective, only
“reasonable,” to avoid liability. See id. at 844 (“[P]rison officials who actually knew of a
substantial risk to inmate health or safety may be found free from liability if they responded
reasonably to the risk, even if the harm ultimately was not averted.”).
148. See, e.g., NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at pt. VIII (reporting that almost half of the fifty
states do not collect data on rapes occurring in their jails and prisons). In any event, such
evidence may be of little value to an inmate attempting to prove official awareness of risk. See,
e.g., Robertson, Clean Heart, supra note 27, at 453 (“[T]he courts have eschewed systemic
analysis . . . .”).
149. See McGill v. Duckworth, 944 F.2d 344, 349 (7th Cir. 1991) (“A prisoner normally
proves actual knowledge of impending harm by showing that he complained to prison officials
about a specific threat to his safety.”).
150. See, e.g., United States v. Bailey, 444 U.S. 394, 426 n.6 (1980) (Blackmun, J., dissenting)
(noting that the life of an inmate who reports a rape or threat of rape “isn’t worth a nickel”)
(citing R. GOLDFARB, JAILS: THE ULTIMATE GHETTO 325–26 (1975)); NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at
pt. VIII (noting the dangers to inmates of reporting rapes and threats of rape); Robertson,
Clean Heart, supra note 27, at 455 (“Notification in this manner comes at great risk to a targeted
inmate: he becomes a snitch.”).
151. Inmates are not guaranteed that their requests for protective custody will be honored.
See, e.g., Robertson, Clean Heart, supra note 27, at 456.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

591

commentator observed, protective custody is “a prison within a prison.”152 In
a typical institution, it “consists of several hours of lockdown, loss of
privileges, and removal from prison activities (i.e., church, educational
programs, movies, work, classes).”153
A further obstacle to legal relief for prison rape victims is the Prison
Litigation Reform Act (“PLRA”).154 Passed in 1996 with the stated goal of
curbing frivolous inmate suits,155 the PLRA significantly curtails the ability of
inmates to sue prison officials over the conditions of confinement. Although
the PLRA does not diminish the rights of prisoners, it places substantial
obstacles in the way of vindicating those rights. In particular, the PLRA
limits inmates’ access to the courts by restricting the availability of attorneys’
fees, and thus attorneys, for successful suits;156 requiring that inmates first
exhaust available prison grievance procedures,157 which are notoriously slow
and ineffectual;158 requiring filing fees even from indigent defendants who
have previously filed unsuccessful claims;159 and limiting the scope and
duration of injunctive remedies for legitimate rights violations.160
Between the Supreme Court’s Eighth Amendment jurisprudence and
the statutory reforms of the PLRA, the current legal environment provides
prison rape victims and would-be victims with little hope of relief from the
courts. But while prevailing doctrine could be modified in various ways to
better accommodate the legitimate grievances of inmates, the problem of
prison rape represents more than a failure of existing legal standards. More
fundamentally, the problem of prison rape, and our indifference to it,
represents a moral failure that implicates us all.

152. Id. at 459–60.
153. Hensley et al., Characteristics, supra note 25, at 604; see also NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at
pt. VIII (likening protective custody conditions to those of disciplinary segregation); Robertson,
Clean Heart, supra note 27, at 460 (noting that “protective custody affords inmates little freedom
of movement, scant programming, and slim prospects for a prison job”). Underscoring the
strong disincentives for inmates to request protective custody, courts have cited high rates of
protective custody in an institution as evidence of pervasive fear of victimization. See, e.g., Jensen
v. Clarke, 94 F.3d 1191, 1197 (8th Cir. 1996) (citing dramatic increases in the number of
inmates in protective custody in concluding that inmates face “a substantial risk of physical
harm”); Ramos v. Lamm, 485 F. Supp. 122, 141 (D. Colo. 1979) (noting that the size of the
protective custody population is “one of the most accurate barometers” of fear in an
institution).
154. Pub. L. No. 104-134, 110 Stat. 1321 (1996) (codified in scattered sections of 18, 28, &
42 U.S.C. (2000)).
155. See, e.g., 142 CONG. REC. 6, 8237 (1996) (statement of Sen. Abraham) (“Our proposals
will return sanity and State control to our prison systems. To begin with, we would institute
several measures to reduce frivolous inmate litigation.”).
156. 42 U.S.C. § 1997e(d) (2000).
157. Id. § 1997e(a).
158. See Robertson, Compassionate Conservatism, supra note 100, at 16.
159. See 28 U.S.C. § 1915(b)(1) (2000).
160. See 18 U.S.C. §§ 3626(a)–(g) (2000); see also NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at pt. VIII.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

592

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

V. RIGHTS, VIRTUE, AND CHARACTER
The commitment to individual rights, reflected in the Eighth
Amendment proscription against cruel and unusual punishment, is a
defining attribute of a liberal democratic society.161 Other important rights
in the context of criminal justice include the right to a jury trial,162 the right
against self-incrimination,163 and the right to be free from unreasonable
search and seizure.164 In these various ways, rights protect individuals against
the awesome power of government by ruling out (or requiring) certain
forms of conduct and treatment.165 Experience suggests that rights are
essential to the pursuit of justice.166
But justice alone may be an insufficient basis for a morally decent
society.167 In the context of prison rape, for example, the commitment to

161. See ROBERT A. DAHL, ON DEMOCRACY 48–50 (1998); MILL, ON LIBERTY, supra note 20,
at 17 (“No society in which these liberties [of conscience, expression, and association] are not,
on the whole, respected, is free, whatever may be its form of government . . . .”). Similarly, John
Locke wrote:
The Reason why Men enter into Society, is the preservation of their [lives, liberties,
and] Property; and the end why they chuse and authorize a Legislative, is, that
there may be Laws made, and Rules set as Guards and Fences to the Properties of
all the Members of the Society, to limit the Power, and moderate the Dominion of
every Part and Member of the Society.
JOHN LOCKE, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT § 222, at 430 (Peter Laslett ed., Cambridge Univ.
Press 1967) (1690).
162. U.S. CONST. amend. VI.
163. U.S. CONST. amend. V.
164. U.S. CONST. amend. IV.
165. That is, legal rights aim to protect individuals from government. Individuals also
possess moral rights, which are not assigned by the legal system, do not depend on the
existence or operation of a legal regime, and hold generally against other individuals. See, e.g.,
JUDITH JARVIS THOMSON, THE REALM OF RIGHTS 2–3 (1990) (noting that even in the absence of
a law against nose-breaking, an individual has a right that others refrain from doing so).
166. See, e.g., DAHL, supra note 161, at 50 (noting the significance of rights for the
maintenance of liberty and justice); JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 4–5 (1971) (same);
MILL, ON LIBERTY, supra note 20, at 7 passim (warning of the dangers, abundant in history, of
the tyranny of the majority).
167. See, e.g., Judith Jarvis Thomson, A Defense of Abortion, 1 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 47, 59–61
(1971) (distinguishing justice from decency). Thomson, in defending a woman’s right to
choose an abortion, notes that particular circumstances may render the exercise of a right
“morally indecent.” Id. at 59. In the context of her now-famous violinist example, Thomson
observes that a person who refuses to sacrifice one hour to save the life of a world-class violinist
who will otherwise die does not act unjustly, but is nevertheless indecent. Id. at 61. To highlight
this distinction, Thomson imagines alternative scenarios involving two young brothers. Id. at
56–61. In the first case, the boys are jointly presented with a box of chocolates. Under these
circumstances (and all other things being equal), each boy has a claim to half of the candy; if
the older boy eats all of it, he acts unjustly. Id. at 56. By contrast, if the older boy is alone
presented with the chocolates and proceeds to eat the entire box in front of his younger
brother, he does not act unjustly but (presumably) indecently; in that event, “he is greedy, stingy,

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

593

rights falls far short of protecting individuals from brutal treatment at the
hands of other inmates. The problem is not—or at least not only—that many
victims will be unable to establish a rights violation under existing legal
standards. The problem, rather, is that with or without an established rights
violation, the rights model cannot take the full measure of the wrongness of
prison rape.168 Having been conditioned to focus on actionable rights
violations, we often respond with indifference to instances of mere suffering.
When we are not directly responsible for harm, we are less inclined to feel
implicated in its infliction. The tendency to distance ourselves in this way is
exacerbated by the unpopularity of the victims of prison rape and the
relative obscurity of the problem.169 Under these circumstances, we are illequipped to notice or care about these instances of profound suffering.
More generally, contemporary liberalism is too often inattentive to the
considerations of virtue and character that might ground a more
compassionate response to the victims of prison rape. After a brief review of
the rights model, a discussion of virtue ethics raises the possibility of
incorporating such considerations into our ethical framework. In the
context of prison rape, the virtue-ethical perspective insists that something
more is at stake than the rights of unpopular inmates—also at stake is our
character. Extrapolating from the conception of character at the heart of
virtue ethics, we will then be in a position to examine the limitations of our
approach to the problem of prison rape in terms of national character.
A. THE RIGHTS MODEL
Among the most influential sources of contemporary liberalism is the
work of Immanuel Kant. Kantianism is generally regarded as a form of
deontology, the view that morality consists in distinctive duties in terms of

callous—but not unjust.” Id. at 60. See generally AVISHAI MARGALIT, THE DECENT SOCIETY (1996)
(arguing that decency is a more urgent and realistic goal for society than justice).
168. Of course, the rape itself constitutes a violation of a moral right, regardless of whether
the rapist or anyone else is held legally liable. See THOMSON, supra note 165, at 1–2. But in the
absence of prosecution or another form of redress, the right will not be vindicated.
169. Although prison rape is a highly visible popular culture phenomenon, see supra Part II,
the problem of prison rape has a relatively low profile. Thus, prison rape has not been widely
studied, see, e.g., Cindy Struckman-Johnson et al., Sexual Coercion Reported by Men, supra note 33,
at 67; the magnitude of the problem remains indeterminate, see, e.g., Robertson, Compassionate
Conservatism, supra note 100, at 7–9; and, according to some officials, the problem has been
greatly exaggerated. See id. (quoting Martin Horn, the commissioner of the New York City
Probation Department’s characterization of the PREA as “the ‘Oz Bill’” because it represents a
similarly unrealistic portrayal of prison life); see also NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at pt. I (noting
that “serious, sustained, and constructive attention to [prison rape] remains rare”). As Stephen
Donaldson, the late President of the organization Stop Prisoner Rape said, “‘the rape of males
is a taboo subject for public discussion. . . . If ever there was a crime hidden by a curtain of
silence, it is male rape.’” NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at pt. I.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

594

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

which right and wrong conduct is defined.170 Thus, the rightness or
wrongness of an act is not determined primarily by the goodness or badness
of the consequences it yields. Certain moral imperatives—prohibitions on
lying, cheating, and stealing, for example—illustrate this feature. As a
general matter, one is enjoined from doing these things regardless of
whether doing them in particular cases would yield better consequences.
According to Kant, human reason is the source of these moral
imperatives.171 On this view, we can have reasons for endorsing only those
principles of action that could be adopted (rationally) by everyone
concerned.172 From this starting point, it is possible to justify the various
duties of persons—the perfect duties—which correlate with the rights of
others.173 Thus, a rational person could not will the adoption of a universal
principle of stealing, because it would render his own property insecure.
The duty to refrain from stealing correlates with the rights of others to be
free from the unauthorized taking of their property.
Kant maintained that people also have imperfect duties—of charity or
benevolence, for example—which do not correspond to the rights of
others.174 Imperfect duties are those that cannot be observed toward all
other persons; no one, for example, can help every person in need. Thus,
though individuals have a duty of charity, no one has a right to another’s
charity. In this way, Kant’s “duties of virtue” require the performance of
certain actions and not others, but they do not specify any particular
character or disposition with which such actions must be undertaken.175 It is
these considerations of character and motive that are the preoccupation of
virtue ethics.

170. See generally David McNaughton, Deontological Ethics, in ROUTLEDGE ENCYCLOPEDIA OF
PHILOSOPHY 890 (Edward Craig ed., 1998).
171. See Onora O’Neill, Kantian Ethics, in ROUTLEDGE ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY, supra
note 170, at 200, 201 (discussing Kant’s conception of practical reasoning).
172. See IMMANUEL KANT, GROUNDWORK OF THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS 88 (Herbert J.
Paton ed., 1961) (1785) (“Act only on that maxim through which you can at the same time will
that it should become a universal law.”).
173. See KANT, THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS, supra note 19.
174. See, e.g., KANT, THE DOCTRINE OF VIRTUE, supra note 19, at 115–22.
175. Recent scholarly work examining Kant’s theory of virtue suggests that this claim may
be too strong. See generally BARBARA HERMAN, THE PRACTICE OF MORAL JUDGMENT (1993)
(offering a reinterpretation of Kantian ethics that emphasizes moral judgment and moral
personality); NANCY SHERMAN, MAKING A NECESSITY OF VIRTUE: ARISTOTLE AND KANT ON VIRTUE
(1997) (tracing the role of emotions and practical wisdom in Aristotelian and Kantian ethics
and finding numerous commonalities); MARK TIMMONS, Motive and Rightness in Kant’s Ethical
System, in KANT’S METAPHYSICS OF MORALS 255 (Mark Timmons ed., 2002) (investigating the
role of motive in Kant’s conception of right action and concluding that motive is relevant to the
rightness of at least some actions).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

595

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE
B. VIRTUE ETHICS

The primary inspiration for contemporary virtue ethics is Aristotle,
whose central insight in his account of ethics was that human flourishing
consists in the exercise of certain virtues.176 For Aristotle, “the good for man
is an activity of soul in accordance with virtue.”177 In its many modern
variants, virtue ethics is often distinguished from alternative ethical
approaches on the grounds that it is agent-centered.178 That is, instead of
asking “What is the right action?” as a rights theorist would do,179 the virtue
ethicist asks “What sort of person should I be?” The short answer, of course,
is that one should be a virtuous person, that is, a person with the disposition
or character to act in some ways and not in others. But one’s actions only
reflect one’s character; they do not constitute it.180 Thus, we cannot conclude
on the basis of a single action, or even a series of actions, that a person is, for
example, courageous, honest, or compassionate. “A virtue, unlike a mere
habit, is a disposition to act for reasons, and so a disposition which is
exercised through the agent’s practical reasoning; it is built up by making
choices and exercised in making further choices.”181 Indeed, “the disposition
in question . . . is multi-track. It is concerned with many other actions as well,
with emotions and emotional reactions, choices, values, desires, perceptions,

176. See ARISTOTLE, NICHOMACHEAN ETHICS (J.A.K. Thomson trans., 1976) (n.d.); Roger
Crisp & Michael Slote, Introduction to VIRTUE ETHICS 1, 2 (Roger Crisp & Michael Slote eds.,
1997); see also ROSALIND HURSTHOUSE, ON VIRTUE ETHICS 8 (1999) [hereinafter HURSTHOUSE,
ON VIRTUE ETHICS].
177. ARISTOTLE, supra note 176, at 76.
178. See, e.g., HURSTHOUSE, ON VIRTUE ETHICS, supra note 176, at 48; Crisp & Slote, supra
note 176, at 3.
179. I have so far distinguished between ethical approaches that depend on duties and
rights on the one hand and consequences on the other. See supra note 18 and accompanying
text. However, I shall relax this distinction for purposes of comparison with virtue ethics on the
grounds that most defensible contemporary accounts of consequentialism, including
utilitarianism, recognize rights as an effective means of maximizing good consequences.
Indeed, this was John Stuart Mill’s approach. See, e.g., MILL, ON LIBERTY, supra note 20, at 19
passim (defending “Liberty of Thought,” including speaking and writing, based on the dire
consequences for individuals and society of failing to protect these liberties against majority
interference). For Mill, and consequentialists generally, rights are likely to be important, but
not fundamental.
180. According to Aristotle:
But virtuous acts are not done in a just or temperate way merely because they have a
certain quality, but only if the agent also acts in a certain state, viz. (1) if he knows
what he is doing, (2) if he choose it, and chooses it for its own sake, and (3) if he
does it from a fixed and permanent disposition.
See ARISTOTLE, supra note 176, at 97.
181. Julia Annas, Virtue Ethics, in OXFORD COMPANION TO ETHICAL THEORY (David Copp
ed., forthcoming 2006).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

596

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

attitudes, interests, expectations and sensibilities.”182 Cultivating the virtues
thus involves bringing “one’s emotions in[to] harmony with one’s rational
recognition of certain reasons for action” and responding with sensitivity to
life’s moral complexity.183
From the perspective of virtue ethics, a key shortcoming of both
deontological and utilitarian ethics is the failure to take adequate account of
this moral complexity.184 On this view, the traditional attempt to reduce
morality to a set of duties and rules that can be followed by any rational
person is inherently futile.185 Because rules of general applicability cannot
possibly accommodate all contingencies, a rule-based ethics necessarily falls
short in the numerous cases where the rules run out.186 By contrast, the
virtue ethicist maintains that moral decision-making requires practical
wisdom, “the capacity to recognize, in any particular situation, those features
of it that are morally salient.”187 In particular, because the “virtues are
concerned with actions and feelings, . . . the moral education needed to
develop them involves the education of the emotions.”188 In this way,
“[o]ccasion by occasion, one knows what to do . . . not by applying universal
principles but by being a certain kind of person: one who sees situations in a
certain distinctive way.”189
A related flaw in rule-based ethics on this view is the failure to account
for the “texture of our moral experience.”190 Recall that the focus of
deontology is determining the right course of action. Thus, in a case of
moral conflict where only one of two valid moral principles can be followed,
the deontological question is: “What is the right thing to do, x or y?” If we
assume that the outcomes associated with x and y are both morally
repugnant, but outcome x is slightly less bad, then the deontologist can

182. Rosalind Hursthouse, Virtue Ethics, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY,
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-virtue/ (last visited Oct. 27, 2005) [hereinafter
Hursthouse, Virtue Ethics).
183. Id.
184. See, e.g., HURSTHOUSE, ON VIRTUE ETHICS, supra note 176, at 18, 59 and passim.
185. See, e.g., id. at 40; Roger Crisp, Virtue Ethics, in ROUTLEDGE ENCYCLOPEDIA OF
PHILOSOPHY, supra note 170, at 622–23 (tracing the development of virtue ethics).
186. See, e.g., ARISTOTLE, supra note 176, at 93 (“[A]ny account of right conduct must be
stated in outline and not in precise detail.”).
187. Hursthouse, Virtue Ethics, supra note 182.
188. HURSTHOUSE, ON VIRTUE ETHICS, supra note 176, at 19.
189. John McDowell, Virtue and Reason, in VIRTUE ETHICS, supra note 176, at 161–62; see also
ARISTOTLE, supra note 176, at 93 (noting that because general rules lack the precision to
address specific situations, “agents are compelled at every step to think out for themselves what
the circumstances demand”).
190. HURSTHOUSE, ON VIRTUE ETHICS, supra note 176, at 55.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

597

readily declare the doing of x “morally right.”191 But in such a case, a morally
right decision does not entail that x is a morally right action, for the doing of x
will itself produce a morally repugnant outcome. This resolution of the
dilemma, though morally correct, fails as a formal matter to accommodate
remorse or regret—the “moral remainder” that such a terrible choice
should yield.192 By way of illustration, Rosalind Hursthouse likens this
phenomenon to the professional shortcomings of certain doctors.193 In a
variety of cases, a patient might complain not about a doctor’s decision, but
about the callous or insensitive way he delivers or acts upon it. “[H]aving
made (what they take to be) the morally right decision, they . . . can review
their conduct with complete satisfaction. But if someone dies, or suffers, or
undergoes frightful humiliation as a result of their decision, even supposing
it is unquestionably correct, surely regret is called for.”194 An ethical
structure that makes no room for such regret at least partly misses the moral
point.
C. PERSONAL VIRTUE AND NATIONAL CHARACTER
Despite the significance of the distinctions between deontology and
virtue ethics, it is not important for present purposes whether the rights
model can—or can be made to—accommodate considerations of motive
and character. It is enough to see that virtue ethics, by placing motive and
character at the center of its ethical model, highlights such considerations in
a way that liberalism, relying on the rights model, traditionally has not. It is
these considerations of motive and character that provide the resources for
examining our complicity in the problem of prison rape.
The traditional domain of virtue ethics is individual morality. That is,
virtue ethics primarily concerns itself with questions about personal virtue—
the sort of person one should be, the dispositions of character one should
cultivate, the kind of life one should lead. In this way, the individual agent,

191.

Hursthouse offers the following example:
The man who has induced two women to bear a child of his by promising
marriage, can only marry one, but may not be in an irresolvable dilemma; it may
be worse to abandon A than B, and let us suppose he makes “the morally right
decision” and marries A, perforce breaking his promise to B and condemning her
child to illegitimacy.

Id. at 46–47. The point, she suggests, is that this man “merits not praise, but blame, for having
created the circumstances that made it necessary for him to abandon B; he should be feeling
ashamed of himself, not proud, and so on.” Id.
192. Id. at 47–48.
193. Id. at 48. The observation could also be applied to lawyers or other professionals who
deal in such high-stakes matters as life, liberty, and death. Id.
194. Id. at 48.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

598

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

and not social rules, is the unit of analysis.195 Thus, Aristotle’s Ethics was
oriented toward how one could become a good person.196 Similarly, the
focus of contemporary virtue ethics is on the moral agent, “a certain sort of
person with a certain complex mindset.”197 As a result, the implications of
personal virtue for contemporary law and politics are less well-developed.198
Despite its traditional focus on personal morality, the central insight of
the virtue ethical tradition has implications as well for the assessment of
national character. In particular, the significance of motive and character in
personal morality has an analog in the life of a nation or people. That is,
what matters is not only what actions nations perform and what policies they
pursue, but the attitudes and dispositions with which they characteristically
undertake such actions and policies. National character thus offers an
additional vantage point from which to assess our response to the problem
of prison rape in the United States.
To establish this, it is first necessary to make sense of character as a
national attribute. The basic idea is an intuitive one, reflected in the
aftermath of the Abu Ghraib prison abuse scandal. In addition, the concept
of national character has been in play for several centuries, though only
loosely and variously articulated. After a brief analysis of the concept, it will
then be possible to assess our own national character and the ways in which
it is implicated in the problem of prison rape.

195. Both deontological and utilitarian ethics also are concerned with the morality of the
agent, but primarily as it concerns the social rules by which they should govern their relations
with one another.
196. ARISTOTLE, supra note 176, at 93. Aristotle, of course, was not only concerned with
personal morality. Because “man is by nature a social being,” id. at 74, Aristotle was also keenly
interested in the political environment conducive to human fulfillment. As Michael White
notes, Aristotle regarded the polis as prior to the individual, but not in the sense that the “‘state’
[is] a sort of organism for the sake of which individual persons exist and function.” MICHAEL J.
WHITE, POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY: AN HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION 48 (2003). Rather, “the polis . . .
is constitutive of the very identity of its citizens as human persons and supplies the necessary
conditions for their living up to that identity.” Id.
197. Hursthouse, Virtue Ethics, supra note 182.
198. See, e.g., HURSTHOUSE, ON VIRTUE ETHICS, supra note 176, at 5–6 (noting the “obvious
gap” in contemporary virtue ethics concerning questions of justice as a “central topic in
political philosophy”); Crisp & Slote, supra note 176, at 24–25 (discussing the challenges of
extending virtue ethics into political morality and citing some recent attempts). Although some
commentators have suggested that communitarian political arrangements are most consistent
with a commitment to virtue, at least some liberal theorists have argued that virtue ethics is also
compatible with liberalism. See DANIEL STATMAN, Introduction to Virtue Ethics, in VIRTUE ETHICS 3,
17–18 (Daniel Statman ed., 1997) (aligning virtue ethics with communitarianism). But see
generally WILLIAM GALSTON, LIBERAL PURPOSES: GOODS, VIRTUES, AND DIVERSITY IN THE LIBERAL
STATE (1991) (making the case for a liberal theory of virtue); Martha Nussbaum, Aristotelian
Social Democracy, in LIBERALISM AND THE GOOD 203 (R. Douglass et al. eds., 1990) (same).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

599

With a few notable exceptions,199 Americans generally reacted with
outrage at the sight of American soldiers mistreating Iraqi prisoners at the
Abu Ghraib prison in Iraq. Shortly after the pictures became public,
President George W. Bush appeared in an interview on Arab television.
Asked about the abuses at Abu Ghraib, he declared: “This is not America.”200
He also insisted that “the actions of these few people do not reflect the
hearts of the American people.”201 Meanwhile, Susan Sontag declared:
“[T]he photographs are us.”202 According to Sontag, “[w]hat is illustrated by
these photographs is as much the culture of shamelessness as the reigning
admiration of unapologetic brutality.”203 Former Vice President Al Gore also
weighed in, claiming that the soldiers’ conduct at Abu Ghraib was
“completely out of keeping with the character and basic nature of the
American people and at odds with the principles on which America
stands.”204 Finally, Andrew Sullivan editorialized that the actions of a few
soldiers at Abu Ghraib were an inadequate basis for calculating “the moral
state of an entire nation.”205 Instead, according to Sullivan, “Abu Ghraib . . .
remind[s] Americans that their virtue is inherent not in their somehow
being better than other people around the world, but in the ability of the
democratic system to flush out and correct inevitable human error.”206
Regardless of the merits of any one of these claims—whether the
photographs are or are not us—each reflects a recognition that we can speak
sensibly, if not uncontroversially, of a national character. Indeed, despite
Sullivan’s admonition against taking the measure of an entire nation based
on the actions of a few, he offered an alternative conception of American

199. See, e.g., Charles Babington, Senator Critical of Focus on Prisoner Abuse, WASH. POST, May
12, 2004, at A18 (“I’m probably not the only one up at this [Senate hearing] table that is more
outraged by the outrage than we are by the treatment.”); id. (“I am also outraged that we have
so many humanitarian do-gooders right now crawling all over these prisons looking for human
rights violations while our troops, our heroes, are fighting and dying.”); The Rush Limbaugh
Show: Babes Doing the Torture in Iraq (Premiere Radio Networks, May 3, 2004), available at
http://mediamatters.org/items/200405050003?is_gsa=1&final=1 (“[I]f you look at these
pictures, I mean, I don’t know if it’s just me, but it looks like anything you’d see Madonna, or
Britney Spears do on stage. Maybe [you can] get an NEA grant for something like this.”).
200. Interview by Alhurra TV with President George W. Bush, supra note 17; see also id.
(“[T]he actions of these few people do not reflect the hearts of the American people.”); Press
Release, The White House, Remarks by President on Iraq and the War on Terror (May 24,
2004), www.whitehouse.gov/news/releases/2004/05/print/20040524-10.html (“[Abu Ghraib]
became a symbol of disgraceful conduct by a few American troops who dishonored our country
and disregarded our values.”).
201. Interview by Alhurra TV with President George W. Bush, supra note 17.
202. Sontag, supra note 17, at 126.
203. Id. at 29.
204. Remarks by Al Gore, Political Action: Democracy in Action, http://www.moveon.org/pac/
gore-rumsfeld-transcript.html (last visited Nov. 20, 2005).
205. Andrew Sullivan, Picture Frame, TNR ONLINE, May 25, 2004, www.tnr.com.
206. Id.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

600

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

national character based on the commitment to democratic principles and
processes. In this way, Sullivan’s account of national character echoes that of
John Stuart Mill.
Mill conceived of national character primarily in terms of shared
“political antecedents; the possession of a national history, and consequent
community of recollections; collective pride and humiliation, pleasure and
regret, connected with the same incidents in the past.”207 On this view,
national community “is at once shaped by circumstances and freely willed, a
product of the evolution of ‘national character’ and an expression of a ‘daily
plebiscite.’”208 In the United States, national character consists (roughly) in
the founding and sustaining documents of our representative form of
government; the historical triumphs, transgressions, and defeats that
constitute our shared past; and the ongoing—if imperfect—commitment to
the processes of democratic accountability.
D. PUNISHMENT AND NATIONAL CHARACTER
The stories we tell about who we are as a people tend to emphasize
these features—liberty, equality, self-government, and self-improvement. In
the context of criminal punishment, the Eighth Amendment’s proscription
against cruel and unusual punishment signals our formal commitment to
the humane and compassionate treatment of all criminal offenders.
Moreover, the Supreme Court has held that criminal punishment must
comport “with the basic concept of human dignity at the core”209 of the
“cruel and unusual punishments” clause, as well as the “evolving standards of
decency that mark the progress of a maturing society.”210 Cruel punishments
are “inconsistent with the fundamental premise of the Clause that even the
vilest criminal remains a human being possessed of common human
dignity.”211 Even with respect to capital punishment, the Court has rejected

207. JOHN STUART MILL, Considerations on Representative Government, in ON LIBERTY, supra
note 20, at 427; see also IMMANUEL KANT, ANTHROPOLOGY FROM A PRAGMATIC POINT OF VIEW
225–36 (Victor Lyle Dowdell trans., S. Ill. U. Press 1978) (1804) (identifying national character
in terms of common roots, self-identification, and inheritance from ancestors); MONTESQUIEU,
THE SPIRIT OF THE LAWS 310 (Anne M. Cohler et al. eds., 1989) (1748) (“Many things govern
men: climate, religion, laws, the maxims of government, examples of past things, mores, and
manners; a general spirit is formed as a result.”).
208. PERICLES LEWIS, MODERNISM, NATIONALISM, AND THE NOVEL 66 (2000).
209. Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153, 182 (1976).
210. Trop v. Dulles, 356 U.S. 86, 101 (1958); see also Woodson v. North Carolina, 428 U.S.
280, 304 (1976) (noting the “fundamental respect for humanity underlying the Eighth
Amendment”).
211. Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 273 (1972) (Brennan, J., concurring) (“The
infliction of an extremely severe punishment . . . from which ‘no circumstance of degradation
[was] omitted,’ may reflect the attitude that the person punished is not entitled to recognition
as a fellow human being.” (quoting Weems v. United States, 217 U.S. 349, 366 (1910)
(alteration in original))).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

601

sentencing schemes that “exclude[ ] from consideration . . . the possibility of
compassionate or mitigating factors stemming from the diverse frailties of
humankind.”212
Despite this morally uplifting storyline, our attitudes and practices
regarding prison rape suggest that our commitment to the humane and
compassionate treatment of criminal offenders may be insincere, or at least
inadequate. Thus, “the astonishing prevalence and tolerance of sexual
violence and subjugation . . . among male prisoners”213 perhaps reveals that
“our commitment to the moral values of order, lawfulness, and security [is]
mere hypocrisy.”214 At a minimum, we seem to have lost sight of the critical
distinction “between really accepting a proposition and simply mouthing the
words.”215 That is, with respect to the institutions of criminal punishment,
“the suffering of others has not become a part of [our] emotional repertory
in such a way that it will influence [our] conduct, provide [us] with motives
and expectations, and so forth.”216 Although we seem to have achieved a
consensus about the correct moral values regarding punishment, we do not
appear to care very much whether these values are actually honored in
practice.
This disjunction between our cherished principles and actual practices
at times seems endemic to criminal punishment in the United States. “We
profess to abhor rape, to adore personal dignity, to uphold the rights of the
downtrodden—yet we sentence tens of thousands of men every year to the
most bestial kind of abuse, without a second thought beyond the occasional
chuckle.”217 Although the reasons for this dissonance cannot be established
with certainty, the most compelling explanations reflect a few common
themes.
One of the earliest attempts to come to terms with this aspect of human
behavior is found in the New Testament, where Jesus repeatedly directs his
followers to refrain from judging others too harshly. Thus, when confronted
with an adulteress, he admonishes the mob that has assembled to punish

212. Woodson, 428 U.S. at 304; see also Furman, 408 U.S. at 413 (expressing worry that the
decision would produce mandatory death statutes that would eliminate “the element of mercy”)
(Blackmun, J., dissenting).
213. Fried, supra note 24, at 682–83.
214. Id. at 687–88.
215. Martha Nussbaum, Compassion: The Basic Social Emotion, 13 SOC. PHIL. & POL’Y 27, 38
(1996).
216. Id. (describing Rousseau’s EMILE).
217. Rich Lowry, The Shame of Our Prisons, TOWNHALL.COM, May 9, 2003,
http://townhall.com; see also Dickey, supra note 96 (describing a running joke on a Los Angeles
radio station regarding prison rape); Robert Teesdale, Project Exile Promotes Prison Rape,
FREEREPUBLIC.COM, May 11, 2001, http://www.freerepublic.com/forum/a3afbfe4a6fa0.htm
(describing public service announcements in Colorado that “make a deliberate point of
suggesting that if you are sent to Federal prison under Project Exile, prison rape will be an
expected part of your future”).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

602

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

her: “He that is without sin among you, let him first cast a stone at her.”218 In
this way, Jesus suggests that the inclination to judge and punish others
harshly inevitably reflects hypocrisy on the part of those who are themselves
imperfect.219 Likewise, in the parable of the unforgiving servant,220 Jesus
illustrates the hypocrisy that can distort our perception of the appropriate
treatment of others. Having been spared by his master the harsh
consequences of his own default, a household servant nevertheless withholds
mercy from his debtor, refusing the compassion that his own creditor
showed him.
In these and other parables, Jesus offers lessons in moral humility that
are equally instructive for the secular law.221 In particular, he recognizes the
potential for self-deception when one human being presumes to judge
another. Such judgments cannot be avoided in the criminal law, but they
can be tempered by the recognition of our own fallibility. In this way, the
teachings of Jesus are, among other things, an exhortation to resist the usversus-them mentality that too often characterizes the institution of criminal
punishment.
In a very different context, Friedrich Nietzsche offered an analysis of
the institution of criminal punishment that similarly underscores the human
potential for self-deception, self-righteousness, and cruelty. Thus, Nietzsche
admonished us to “[m]istrust all in whom the impulse to punish is
powerful.”222 According to Nietzsche, what lies behind our retributive
judgments is ressentiment—a volatile mix of resentment, fear, cowardice,
cruelty, envy, hypocrisy, and self-deception (among other things).223
Punishment, on this view, is simply an excuse for venting these emotions and
delighting in the suffering of others—a “warrant and title to cruelty.”224
Nietzsche, of course, was not advocating compassion or mercy, which he
regarded as slave emotions.225 Instead, the value of his insight is the
recognition that as a psychological matter, human beings have the capacity
for both cruelty and rationalization. In the context of punishment, this
should cause us to question whether our zeal for justice actually reflects
emotions that we officially reject in the criminal law, such as spite, malice,
218. John 8:7.
219. Matthew 7:1–11.
220. Matthew 18:23–35.
221. See Jeffrie G. Murphy, Moral Epistemology, the Retributive Emotions, and the “Clumsy Moral
Philosophy” of Jesus Christ, in PASSIONS OF LAW 149, 160 (Susan Bandes ed., 1999).
222. FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, in THE PORTABLE NIETZSCHE 103, 212
(Walter Kaufmann trans., 1970).
223. See generally FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE, On the Genealogy of Morals, in BASIC WRITINGS OF
NIETZSCHE 439 (Walter Kaufmann trans., 1967) [hereinafter NIETZSCHE, Genealogy]; see also
Moore, Moral Worth, supra note 110, at 106 (describing the “reactive affects” that, according to
Nietzsche, constitute ressentiment).
224. NIETZSCHE, Genealogy, supra note 223, at 501.
225. Id. at 455, 472–75.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

603

envy, and revenge. Indeed, to the extent that the passion for justice and the
penchant for cruelty spring from a common emotional source, we should
proceed with the utmost caution.
A similar insight is reflected in the work of Martha Nussbaum, who
cautions against the excesses of the “we/them mentality, in which judges set
themselves above offenders, looking at their actions from a lofty height and
preparing to find satisfaction in their pain.”226 In extreme cases, one “who
notes and reacts to every injustice, and who becomes preoccupied with
assigning just punishments, becomes, in the end, oddly similar to the raging
ungentle people against whom he reacts.”227 In this way, the zeal to punish
wrongdoers as harshly as possible may render the punisher (or reveal him to
be) himself vicious.228 The danger, as Judge Posner reminds us, is that we
will come to view offenders as “members of a different species, indeed as a
type of vermin, devoid of human dignity and entitled to no respect.”229 Were
we to adopt this view, “then no issue concerning the degrading or
brutalizing treatment of prisoners would arise.”230
The tendencies captured in these analyses are human and by no means
unique to particular peoples or forms of government. In the United States,
the commitment to the rule of law and individual rights stands as a powerful
check on the cruel and inhumane treatment of criminal offenders. But to
the extent that the rights model neglects questions of character and motive,
226. Martha Nussbaum, Equity and Mercy, in PUNISHMENT AND REHABILITATION, supra note
12, at 212, 229; see also Johnson v. Phelan, 69 F.3d 144, 152 (7th Cir. 1995) (Posner, C.J.,
dissenting) (warning against the tendency to draw a sharp distinction between the law-abiding
(“us”) and criminal offenders (“them”), reserving our compassion only for those with whom we
most readily identify).
227. Nussbaum, supra note 226, at 227.
228. This seems an apt characterization of Bill Lockyer’s response to the alleged
wrongdoing of Enron’s Ken Lay—hoping (publicly) that Lay might be raped in prison. See supra
notes 3, 96 and accompanying text. A particularly vivid historical illustration is related by
Seneca:
Lysimachus . . . [was not] a whit more kind when he himself became king . . . for
Telephorus the Rhodian, his own friend, he completely mutilated, and when he
had cut off his ears and nose, he shut him up in a cage as if he were some strange
and unknown animal and for a long time lived in terror of him, since the
hideousness of his hacked and mutilated face had destroyed every appearance of a
human being; to this were added starvation and squalor and the filth of a body left
to wallow in its own dung; further more, his hands and knees becoming all
calloused—for by the narrowness of his quarters he was forced to use these instead
of feet—his sides a mass of sores from rubbing, to those who beheld him his
appearance was no less disgusting than terrible, and having been turned by his
punishment into a monster he had forfeited even pity. Yet, while he who suffered
these things was utterly unlike a human being, he who inflicted them was still less
like one.
SENECA, 1 MORAL ESSAYS 299–301 (John W. Basore trans., Harvard Univ. Press 1958) (55 A.D.).
229. Johnson, 69 F.3d at 150.
230. Id.

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

604

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

we can expect the rules to fall short in various ways. Thus, in the context of
prison rape, we can point to a rule, such as the Eighth Amendment, against
the inhumane treatment of prisoners. In the face of an injunction of this
sort, such conduct is categorically off-limits. The problem then becomes
specifying precisely what the abstract prohibition on cruelty forbids.231 This
is complicated, in turn, by the indirect nature of the abuse, which allows
guards, officials, and the public to deny responsibility for the victims’
suffering.232 Moreover, once the Supreme Court declares that the Eighth
Amendment requires some threshold level of treatment (X), we have very
few resources for insisting that X is morally unacceptable and that a more
humane level of treatment is morally appropriate for prisoners than what
their rights have been interpreted to require. In such a case, the
constitutional pronouncement conditions us to adopt the bare minimum as
our standard of decency.
The considerations of motive and character that animate virtue ethics,
by contrast, call our attention to the suffering of prison rape victims and the
indifference—and worse—with which we have typically responded. In
particular, such considerations remind us that morality is not exhausted by
the determination of whether a right has been respected or violated. For in
exercising or respecting a moral right, we may nevertheless “do something
cruel, or callous, or selfish, light-minded, self-righteous, stupid,
inconsiderate, disloyal, dishonest—that is, act viciously.”233
In the context of prison rape, the threat to character associated with
such attitudes can take a variety of forms. First, as already suggested, prison
rape almost certainly corrupts the character of the inmates themselves, rape
victims and perpetrators alike. Regardless of whether it violates their rights,
it is indecent to consign human beings to an environment where they are
likely to be degraded by others or (further) degrade themselves. By treating
wrongdoers this way, we effectively eliminate any chance of restoring them
to correct moral values or instilling in them a respect for the physical and
psychological integrity of other persons.234 Instead, if they are paying
attention, they will learn that human life lacks intrinsic value, that the strong

231. See, e.g., ARISTOTLE, supra note 176, at 93 (“Now questions of conduct and expedience
have as little fixity about them as questions about what is healthful; and if this is true of the
general rule, it is still more true that its application to particular problems admits of no
precision.”).
232. See Pogge, supra note 45, at 194 (suggesting that unlike private wrongdoing, people
tend to see governmental violation of rights as “everyone’s concern and feel implicated in, and
experience shame on account of, what their government and its officials do in their name”).
233. HURSTHOUSE, Virtue Theory and Abortion, in ON VIRTUE ETHICS, supra note 176, at 217,
227.
234. See, e.g., Morris, supra note 125, at 166 (“Punishments that are aimed at degrading or
brutalizing a person are not conducive to moral awakening but only to bitterness and
resentment.”).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

605

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

can have their way by preying on the weak, and that the concern of the
human community extends only to those who never transgress its laws.
In addition, as Kant suggested, the tolerance (and worse) of prison rape
can be expected to corrupt the character of those responsible for the
administration, implementation, and oversight of penal institutions. For if
rape and torture are “themselves . . . punishable crimes against humanity,”235
the creation and maintenance of prison conditions that foster them must
compromise “the moral integrity of the officials who have to administer the
penal system.”236 Moreover, “insofar as our existing penal institutions and
practices are . . . radically unjust, oppressive, or morally corrupt . . . they put
all of us in a morally problematic position.”237 In a self-governing society,
where criminal punishment is imposed in our name, such pervasive
corruption is bound to taint us all.238
Finally, and perhaps most worrisome, the problem of prison rape—
especially our attitudes about it—reflects the corruption that has already
taken root in our national character. Despite the principles and practices by
which we define ourselves—especially our commitment to due process and
humane, proportionate punishment—the cruelty and indifference
characteristic of criminal punishment in the United States bespeak a more
vicious disposition.
VI. CONCLUSION
My central claim has been that the considerations of motive and
character that are at the heart of virtue ethics add an important dimension
to our understanding of the problem of prison rape in the United States
without displacing more familiar rights-based considerations. Indeed, the
Eighth Amendment represents an important affirmation that the gratuitous
infliction of suffering constitutes an intolerable violation of a fundamental
right. But the public’s indifference to the fate of prison inmates does not
violate anyone’s rights; it is more insidious than that. For in our failure to
care about the suffering of these victims—and in our penchant to make
jokes about it—we exhibit a degree of callousness that signals the corruption
of our character.
It is unclear whether incorporating the virtue-ethical considerations will
have any direct legal consequences, but by asking a different set of
questions—about who we are and what is acceptable to us—we may discover

235. KANT, METAPHYSICAL ELEMENTS, supra note 116, at *363.
236. Waldron, supra note 13, at 38.
237. R.A. Duff, Penance, Punishment and the Limits of Community, 5 PUNISHMENT & SOC’Y 295,
304 (2003).
238. See Pogge, supra note 45, at 198 (observing that “especially in democratic societies . . .
the people are [the] ultimate guardian on which [the] fulfillment [of human rights] crucially
depends”); id. (noting that the protection of human rights significantly “depends on the
character of [a society’s] people”).

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

606

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

91 IOWA LAW REVIEW

[2006]

a broader range of solutions. In particular, by seeing the problem of prison
rape at least partly as a failure of national will, we may come to see in the
efforts to alleviate the suffering of these victims the vindication of our own
values. The Prison Rape Elimination Act of 2003 may reflect just such a shift
in attitude.239 Its stated purpose is to establish a zero-tolerance standard for
prison rape,240 but its practical effects are mostly symbolic—creating a
federal commission,241 mandating reporting by state corrections officials,242
and establishing a national clearinghouse for data and information on the
incidence of prison rape.243 Although critics have questioned the efficacy of
these measures,244 Congress’s willingness to address the problem represents
a significant, if modest, step toward reform.
Indeed, attending to the suffering of prison rape victims does not mean
that we must immediately divert resources from schools and health care to
prisons, or that the problem of prison rape should become our top
legislative priority. In an environment of scarce resources, it is natural to
prefer the needs of law-abiding citizens. Still, if our formal commitment to
humane prison conditions is to mean anything, we cannot continue to
ignore the problem of prison rape. As a first step, we should experience
deep regret over the necessity for the difficult policy judgments that
contribute to the shameful state of our prisons and see them for the morally
flawed actions they are. Instead, we seem to take a sort of satisfaction in our
self-righteousness, congratulating ourselves and our officials for denying
inmates a minimally decent living environment.245

239. 42 U.S.C. §§ 15601–09 (2003).
240. Id. § 15602(1).
241. Id. § 15603(b).
242. Id. § 15603(a)(6).
243. Id. § 15604(a)(1).
244. See, e.g., Robert Weisberg & David Mills, Violence Silence, SLATE, Oct. 1, 2003,
http://slate.msn.com/id/2089095 (“The reason you’ve never heard of the Prison Rape
Elimination Act is probably that no one who knows our criminal justice system believes it will do
much of anything to eliminate prison rape.”).
245. See, e.g., Neil Chandler, Sheriff Joe on the Run, DAILY STAR (U.K.), Feb. 20, 2005 (noting
that in Arizona, Maricopa County Sheriff Joe Arpaio has saved money by “slashing spending on
jail food” and boasting that “he spends more on grub for the guard dogs”). Sheriff Joe Arpaio is
the most popular elected official in Arizona:
Sheriff Joe Arpaio has dominated Arizona’s popularity ratings in the O’Neil
Associates Valley Monitor since he was first elected. His “most popular” status has
continued in the poll that was just completed. Arpaio’s overall approval
(excellent/good ratings) of 69% is substantially higher than that of Janet
Napolitano (59%) and massively higher than that of Governor Jane Hull (32%).
O’NEIL ASSOCIATES, INC., Arpaio Still Most Popular Arizona Elected Official, O’NEIL ASSOCIATES
VALLEY MONITOR, http://www.oneilresearch.com/ (last visited April 13, 2005); see also Michael
Lockwood & Rachel Alexander, What’s Really Happening in Arpaio’s Jail?,
http://www.intellectualconservative.com/article1005.html (last visited Oct. 27, 2005)

SIGLER_FINAL.DOC

BY THE LIGHT OF VIRTUE

3/1/2006 2:05:25 PM

607

These public attitudes about inmates—the strong us-versus-them
mentality and the inevitable prison rape jokes—translate into public policy
in a variety of ways. For example, public indifference to prison rape victims is
almost certainly reflected in the reluctance of officials to prosecute
offenders. Prosecutors tend to be elected officials with little incentive to
champion the cause of such unpopular victims.246 Thus, “[a]lthough local
prosecutors are nominally responsible for prosecuting criminal acts that
occur in prisons, they are unlikely to consider prisoners part of their real
constituency.”247 As a result, prosecutions of prison rape are exceedingly
rare, and perpetrators can realistically expect to commit the offense
“without fear of spending additional time in prison.”248 The wholesale failure
to prosecute inmates who victimize other inmates cannot be reconciled with
any defensible conception of justice. Mocking the plight of such victims is
positively indecent.
The purpose of invoking virtue and character in the context of prison
rape is not to keep people from telling or laughing at prison rape jokes. The
point, rather, is to remember the attributes by which we define ourselves,
including the commitment to the humane treatment of all persons. It is this
ideal, embedded in our documents, institutions, and traditions, that
constitutes our national character at its best. And it is our character that we
compromise when we fail to be even minimally decent.

(characterizing Sheriff Arpaio’s critics as preferring that he “coddle prisoners by giving them
Hustler magazine and cable television”).
246. See, e.g., NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at pt. VIII (“Prisoners have no political power of
their own, and impunity for abuses against prisoners does not directly threaten the public
outside of prison.”); Dickey, supra note 96, at 44 (“‘Helping inmates is nuclear waste
politically.’” (quoting Vincent Schiraldi, President of the Justice Policy Institute)).
247. NO ESCAPE, supra note 9, at pt. VIII.
248. Id. Consider, for example, the case of “M.R.,” documented in Human Rights Watch’s
2001 report on the problem of prison rape in the United States. Id. at pt. V. After M.R. reported
to prison officials that he was raped by his cell mate, his complaint was dismissed by prison
investigators as a “lovers’ quarrel.” Id. M.R. was repeatedly victimized for a period of several
months with increasing violence each time. Id. In the final attack, M.R. was set upon by his
attacker in the prison’s common room; he was raped and severely beaten in front of dozens of
other inmates, sustaining a broken neck, jaw, and collarbone as well as two serious concussions
and bleeding of the brain. Id. Despite M.R.’s efforts to have his attacker prosecuted, no criminal
charges were ever brought. Id. Instead, the attacker reportedly received fifteen days in
segregation for rape and attempted murder. Id.

 

 

Stop Prison Profiteering Campaign Ad 2
CLN Subscribe Now Ad
PLN Subscribe Now Ad