Skip navigation
PYHS - Header

Dulr Cassell Balanced Approaches to False Confessions 1997

Download original document:
Brief thumbnail
This text is machine-read, and may contain errors. Check the original document to verify accuracy.
Page 1

LEXSEE 74 DENV. U L. REV. 1123
Copyright (c) 1997 University of Denver (Colorado Seminary) College of Law
Denver University Law Review
1997
74 Denv. U.L. Rev. 1123
LENGTH: 6539 words
SYMPOSIUM ON COERCION: AN INTERDISCIPLINARY EXAMINATION OF COERCION, EXPLOITATION,
AND THE LAW: II. COERCED CONFESSIONS: Balanced Approaches to the False Confession Problem: A Brief
Comment on Ofshe, Leo, and Alschuler
NAME: Paul G. Cassell *
BIO:
* Professor of Law, Univ. of Utah College of Law. B.A., 1981, J.D., 1984, Stanford University. I thank
Professors Ofshe and Leo for gracious access to prepublication drafts of their various articles and the editors of
the Denver University Law Review for inviting me to participate in this symposium. Symposium, Coercion: An
Interdisciplinary Examination of Coercion, Exploitation, and the Law, 74 Denv. U. L. Rev. 875 (1997).

SUMMARY:
... Their proposal may, therefore, either have too little "bite" or too much--that is, it may do nothing to solve any false
confession problem or it may "solve" that problem at the expense of producing more serious unintended consequences.
... For instance, the leading police interrogation manual recommends that, at the start of each interrogation, "the
interrogator should finger though the case folder to create the impression that it contains material of an incriminating
nature . . . ." Is that a prohibited "misrepresentation" of the strength of the evidence? Nor is it clear that Alschuler's
proposed rule would do much to solve any false confession problem that might exist. ... For example, there seems to be
virtual unanimity among those who have reviewed the problem that videotaping interrogations is an effective solution to
the false confession problem. ... Videotaping is the best remedy for the false confession problem because it allows
reconstruction of what happened during interrogation and identification of suspects who have been induced to spout
back information supplied by the police. ... The relaxation will not enlarge any false confession problem as exists. ...
TEXT:
[*1123]
The editors have offered me a chance to provide a brief comment on two disparate but intriguing papers on
coercion during policy interrogation--one by Professors Richard Ofshe and Richard Leo, n1 the other by Professor
Albert Alschuler. n2 A short comment cannot possibly do justice to all of the valuable insights in these articles or tie
all their divergent strands neatly together. The papers undeniably offer important perspectives on, respectively, the
psychological processes involved in police questioning and the legal doctrine surrounding it. No doubt they will be--and

Page 2
74 Denv. U.L. Rev. 1123, *1123

should be--widely read and discussed. But the expected role of a commentator is not to praise articles but critique them,
so my observations will be confined to the most important practical strand of the arguments: that police questioning
should be restricted to prevent frequently occurring miscarriages of justice from false confessions.
At least as presented here, n3 a gap in the articles' arguments is that they appear to reason "dramatically, not
quantitatively," as Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes once put it. n4 Proceeding from a few dramatic examples of false
confessions that led to wrongful convictions, the authors suggest substantial changes in current confession doctrine.
Those inclined to oppose such proposals, however, will suggest that policy reforms must be justified with more careful
thinking about both the frequency of false confessions and any offsetting--and potentially larger--costs that might
follow from the restrictions. After all, devising appropriate rules governing the coerciveness of police interrogation
requires striking a balance between the competing concerns of protecting suspects and securing public safety. In
assessing the Supreme Court's [*1124] decision in Miranda v. Arizona, n5 for example, Professor Wertheimer chides
both Chief Justice Warren's majority opinion and the views of the dissenting Justices for failing to forthrightly discuss
the conflicts between the rights of suspects to be free from improper coercion and society's "interest in security." n6
Perhaps in recognition of such critiques, in later opinions the Court has been more candid about the tradeoffs. The Court
now openly describes the Miranda doctrine as a "carefully crafted balance designed to fully protect both the defendant's
and society's interest." n7 While doubts have been raised about whether the Court has really undertaken such balancing
n8 and whether its proper role is to do so, n9 academic commentators proposing restructuring of police interrogation
on normative grounds should certainly consider such factors. Moreover, these calculations involve largely empirical
judgments. Again, as Professor Wertheimer has demonstrated, the moral problem involved in unintentionally punishing
the innocent is one to be resolved on utilitarian judgments, rather than a priori considerations of justice: "The numbers
do count, and in virtually all moral problems in which we sense a conflict between justice and utility, we are prepared to
concede that there is some point at which utility will take precedence." n10
To prevent misunderstandings before going any further, let me make clear my personal view that each miscarriage
from a false confession is a grave tragedy; indeed, I am on record pushing for measures to reduce their incidence. n11
But in the public policy world, concern about miscarriages from false confessions is no substitute for logical thinking
about their frequency and about any offsetting costs that might stem from restrictions on police interrogation. Failing to
think carefully about such issues creates, as I suggest below, n12 the grave danger of inhibiting reform, by producing
politically infeasible suggestions while overlooking more realistic and cost-beneficial alternatives. Without close
attention to what Professor Wertheimer calls "the numbers," the articles' policy suggestions will not be taken seriously
by those who actually have the power to implement them.
The first question that comes to mind while reading these articles is whether wrongful convictions from false
confessions are pervasive or isolated? To briefly set the stage, recall that Professor Alschuler recommends at least
[*1125] one additional restraint on police interrogation. While the bulk of his paper is a superb demonstration that
constitutional "voluntariness" doctrine must focus on police methods--not the psyches of criminal defendants n13
--Alschuler detours briefly into the conclusion that courts "should forbid falsifying evidence and misrepresenting the
strength of the incriminating evidence against a suspect." n14 Alschuler would have the courts adopt this rule as a
matter of constitutional principle, n15 relying on a cross reference to his brilliant article about the historical origins of
the Fifth Amendment. n16 This recommendation stems not (at least as I understand it) from any overarching moral
queasiness about police deception. Alschuler keenly observes that American law on confessions "sometimes seems to
rest on an etiquette more refined than Mrs. Astor's." n17 Given the pressing need for police to develop evidence to
support criminal convictions, he suggests that police perhaps "should be allowed to express false sympathy for the
suspect, blame the victim, and play on the suspect's religious feelings," n18 among other things. But
misrepresentations about evidence stand in a different category largely because of Alschuler's empirical premise such
tactics are "likely to generate false confessions," especially "when suspects are retarded or easily suggestible." n19
Ofshe and Leo take a similar tack. After developing a detailed psychological model of the decision to confess (with
fascinating and generally unavailable insights into what really happens during modern policy interrogation), they
conclude with policy proposals. Based on the premises that "false confessions still occur regularly," n20 that

Page 3
74 Denv. U.L. Rev. 1123, *1125

psychological police interrogation tactics are "apt to cause an innocent suspect to confess, n21 and that false
confessions are "likely to cause the wrongful conviction and imprisonment of an innocent person," n22 Ofshe and Leo
recommend a series of reforms: including judicial screening of the "reliability" of confessions, n23 greater police
training to avoid eliciting false confessions, n24 and videotaping of police interrogations. n25 The important point,
for present purposes, is that the recommendations in both articles hinge directly on the empirical claim that certain
police tactics are apt to produce false confessions leading to miscarriages of justice.
My reading of these articles is that the empirical linchpin for their propos- [*1126] als is simply missing.
Professor Alschuler reports little evidence on this point, relying primarily on a few general references to Professors
Ofshe and Leo's articles to support the claim. n26 Ofshe and Leo, in turn, argue that wrongful convictions from false
confessions are "numerous." n27 But burrowing through the footnotes attached to these claims, it appears that their
primary empirical support is a soon-to-be published paper where these matters are discussed at greater length. n28 The
reader of the current article is essentially left a promissory note that this proof will be supplied in the future. Because
that future paper will be published shortly in another journal where I will be writing a detailed response, n29 I will not
address the frequency of miscarriages from false confessions any further here. But it should be noted that the frequency
claim is not proven in Ofshe and Leo's current article. While bearing the title "The Decision to Confess Falsely," the
article turns out (on reading of the footnotes) to discuss not solely the dramatic subject of those who confess falsely.
The reader will have difficulty knowing which topic is under discussion as Ofshe and Leo explain that "we often choose
not to indicate whether the quoted material was taken from the interrogation of an innocent or a guilty party." n30 The
article thus cannot be cited (as Professor Alschuler may have uncritically done n31 ) to support propositions about
false confessions, because Ofshe and Leo have chosen--rather unhelpfully, in my view--not to separate the two here.
Even apart from the issue of the frequency of false confessions, however, Ofshe, Leo, and Alschuler's justification
of their proffered remedies appears incomplete. Ofshe and Leo's centerpiece proposal is that courts should carefully
evaluate the reliability of a confession by ensuring that it fits with the facts of the crime and is otherwise credible.
Rather than "create any new rules or [*1127] rely on any cumbersome procedures," n32 they propose that courts
should conduct this review under existing rules.
The examples in the article must be put into some perspective. Ofshe and Leo discuss transcripts of police
interrogation of roughly 35 different suspects--both innocent and guilty--primarily from a ten-year period, 1987 to 1997,
n33 although some of the examples are nearly a quarter of a century old. n34 Even looking solely to the last ten years,
police officers around the country interrogated approximately 23 million suspects for index crimes. n35 The 35
interrogations discussed in the Ofshe-Leo paper are quite literally a few drops in this very large bucket.
Evaluating the proposal is quite difficult because Ofshe and Leo do little to explain how it would work in practice.
For example, a regrettable omission from the article is even a single illustration of how their proposed test would have
applied to any of the confessions they discuss. Their proposal may, therefore, either have too little "bite" or too
much--that is, it may do nothing to solve any false confession problem or it may "solve" that problem at the expense of
producing more serious unintended consequences.
Turning to the first possibility, Ofshe and Leo seem unaware that evidence rules conventionally admit relevant
evidence and cannot be used as a basis for courts to screen out evidence they find to lack credibility. n36 A typical
case is Ballou v. Henrie Studies, Inc. n37 There the Fifth Circuit reviewed a district court decision excluding a blood
alcohol test in a civil case alleging negligent driving. n38 The district court had viewed the test result skeptically,
excluding it because it lacked credibility. n39 The Fifth Circuit, following what is clearly the conventional approach in
these matters, n40 would have none of it [*1128] and reversed the district court's decision to exclude. n41 The Fifth
Circuit explained that credibility determinations are not permitted under the rules, discussing Rule 403 (the best "hook"
for the Ofshe-Leo proposal):
We have recently held that Rule 403 does not permit exclusion of evidence because the judge does not find it
credible. Weighing probative value against unfair prejudice under Rule 403 means probative value with respect to a

Page 4
74 Denv. U.L. Rev. 1123, *1128

material fact if the evidence is believed, not to the degree the court finds it believable. Rather than discounting the
probative value of the test results on the basis of its perception of the degree to which the evidence was worthy of belief,
the district court should have determined the probative value of the test results if true, and weighed that probative value
against the danger of unfair prejudice, leaving to the jury the difficult choice of whether to credit the evidence. n42
Applying this reasoning to disputed confession evidence, it is clear that Rule 403, among other rules, can virtually
never serve as the basis for exclusion. The confession "if true" (as the Fifth Circuit put it) provides powerful evidence of
guilt and therefore has high "probative value." Rule 403 permits exclusion only if this high probative value is
"substantially" outweighed by unfair prejudice, a balance that weighs heavily in favor of admitting evidence. Moreover,
the unfair prejudice the rule refers to does not mean the effect on the jury from hearing evidence that might be untrue.
Such concerns, as the Fifth Circuit and many other courts have phrased it, go "to the weight and not the admissibility of
the evidence." n43 In short, the rules--as conventionally interpreted--offers little chance for a defendant to exclude
disputed confession evidence.
Perhaps Ofshe and Leo could reformulate their proposal by devising something other than existing approaches as
the basis of exclusion--although this would involve creating (in their words) "new rules" and "cumbersome procedures."
But even if the courts could somehow be empowered to substitute their own credibility determinations for that of jurors,
Ofshe and Leo will surely need to further develop their argument. They do not discuss how judges should decide cases
in which the prosecution and defense legitimately view the confession differently. They instead focus on the almost
trivial case of a "demonstrably unreliable confession," arguing it is likely to confuse the jury. n44 But if a confession is
truly "demonstrably" unreliable, one would assume that this "demonstration" could be made for the benefit of the jury,
which (given the proof beyond a reasonable doubt standard) would promptly acquit the defendant, particularly where
there was no other evidence against the defendant. Juries do not automatically convict defendants who have reportedly
"confessed"--even looking solely at the cases featured here by Ofshe and Leo. n45 [*1129] To make their argument
fly, Ofshe and Leo need to demonstrate both that courts can accurately exclude false confessions while properly
admitting the true ones and, further, that it is appropriate to divest juries of decisionmaking power on such a critical
issue. If Ofshe and Leo attempt such a demonstration, they will need to confront the argument nicely made by Professor
Alschuler, who in general sees little reason to take the reliability issue from the jury. As he explains, in our system "the
trial of all Crimes . . . shall be by Jury," n46 and therefore "permitting a jury rather than a judge to assess the
evidentiary value of an appropriately obtained confession seems fully compatible with due process." n47 Indeed, the
idea of allowing the judge to exclude supposedly incredible evidence would, leading authorities have commented, be "a
remarkable innovation" n48 and "invade the jury's province and usurp its function." n49
Professor Alschuler would seemingly abandon this long-standing general principle, however, when police resort to
false claims to obtain a confession. Unlike Ofshe and Leo (who would allow "credible" confessions obtained through
such tactics to go to the jury), Alschuler would require the courts to exclude all confessions obtained through police
deception about incriminating evidence, even when the confessions are indisputably truthful. Given that Alschuler
would create yet another exclusionary rule for defendants, he needs to explain specifically how courts across the
country would adjudicate what are sure to be numerous claims that police questioning involved some sort of "false"
evidence, a cost that in itself promises to be considerable. n50 For instance, the leading police interrogation manual
recommends that, at the start of each interrogation, "the interrogator should finger though the case folder to create the
impression that it contains material of an incriminating nature . . . ." n51 Is that a prohibited "misrepresentation" of the
strength of the evidence? Nor is it clear that Alschuler's proposed rule would do much to solve any false confession
problem that might exist. Ofshe and Leo (who provide what empirical support exists for Alschuler's recommendations)
specifically disclaim any such approach, explaining that because false confessions come from the "improper use of
interrogation as a whole, no single procedure can be proscribed and thereby adequately protect the innocent." n52
Alschuler also fails to explore how many truthful confessions would be lost or later suppressed under his proposal
in the quest to prevent a false one. [*1130] The available data raise some concern on this point. Professor Leo's
interesting study is the only recent observational research on what actually happens during police interrogation in this
country. In 30% of the interrogations he watched, police confronted suspects with "false evidence of guilt." n53 If we

Page 5
74 Denv. U.L. Rev. 1123, *1130

can generalize from his sample, three out of every ten police interrogations in this country would have to be restructured
to comply with Alschuler' proposal. Moreover, the Leo data strongly suggest that this restructuring would be costly to
society. Leo found that, while confronting suspects with false evidence was apparently not among the most successful
tactics in every case, n54 for suspects with prior felony records or below middle class status such tactics led to
confessions at rate higher than the norm. n55 While Leo's figures do not permit exact quantification, they plainly
suggest that such tactics are particularly useful in obtaining truthful confessions when dealing with hardened criminals
or lower social class suspects.
This conclusion is supported by one of the few existing observational studies of police interrogation in Britain. The
study reported that while officers generally tried to stick "as close to the truth as possible, . . . informational bluffs are
understood and used in a more sophisticated manner than any other single kind of interviewing tactic. When properly
used their effectiveness in obtaining confessions is beyond doubt, and much of the preparation for an important
interview is aimed at providing a basis for their use." n56 As the proponent of change (indeed, a virtually
unprecedented change), Alschuler has yet to meet his burden of explaining why the benefits of his proposal outweigh
the tangible costs of preventing police from using this valuable questioning technique. n57 Indeed, even focusing
exclusively on innocent suspects, it is not clear whether the restriction would be justifiable. Any restraint that reduces
the [*1131] number of confessions from guilty criminals creates the risk that innocent persons might be erroneously
charged in their stead. n58
Professors Ofshe and Leo similarly fail to consider offsetting costs in arguing that courts should undertake
"credibility" determinations of confessions. If their proposal is fleshed out to frequently prevent the admissibility of
"false" confessions, then it may have too much "bite"--that is, it may exclude so many truthful confessions that it would
be undesirable. Again, a thorough assessment of this possibility is difficult because Ofshe and Leo spend virtually no
time discussing any possible negative effects from their proposal and citations to explanatory legal authorities are few
and far between. Yet courts no less than police investigators can err and, when the errors involve the admissibility of
evidence critical to the prosecution of criminal cases, costs to society are sure to follow in train. If their proposal is to
make any real inroads on false confessions, it seems likely that a good number of truthful confessions would have to be
excluded as well. Some sense of the potential risks comes from a study by Britain's Royal Commission on Criminal
Justice. The Commission concluded that a rule requiring corroboration of a confession for a conviction would reduce
convictions of apparently guilty defendants by as much as 3.1%. n59 If Ofshe and Leo hope to have policy proposal
seriously considered, they will have to explicitly address such concerns.
The apparent failure of Professors Ofshe, Leo, and Alschuler to consider offsetting costs to their proposals n60
seems to be a common feature of suggestions from academics that police interrogation needs to be reined in. In the law
reviews and psychological journals, one can read a veritable stream of new ideas for restricting--or even
eliminating--police interrogation. n61 Academics [*1132] generally advance such suggestions not from
historically-based constitutional principles, but rather policy-based normative ones. n62 But persuasive normative
argument requires attention to not only the pros and but also the cons and striking a reasonable balance between
contending interests. Modern academics give the impression of having little time to tarry over mundane concerns that
guilty criminals might escape justice; most academics prefer to move immediately to a one-sided assessment of the risks
that innocent persons might be convicted or defendants treated unfairly. n63 Professor Caplan's observation about the
police interrogation literature ten years ago continues to ring true today, with regard to the articles in this Symposium
and many others elsewhere: "Unlike the discussions of perceived police abuse, in which passion abounds, the passing
references to the possibility of uncaught murderers and rapists are flat." n64
Perhaps the academics will be successful in advancing such one-sided policy proposals for reforming police
interrogation, but I have my doubts. This fact can be confirmed by the actions of the elected representatives of the
people, who seem to be more interested in freeing the police from restrictions than imposing new ones. n65 Indeed,
even unelected and unaccountable judges (frequently drawn from the ranks of the academics) seem generally reluctant
to impose the wisdom of the law journals on everyday police operations.

Page 6
74 Denv. U.L. Rev. 1123, *1132

While the failure of scholarly proposals to advance is no novelty, there is something troubling about the failure in
this area. If wrongful convictions from false confessions are frequently occurring, then something should be done about
it. Yet the one-sided approach of academics gives short shrift to more balanced suggestions that have a more realistic
chance of adoption. For example, there seems to be virtual unanimity among those who have reviewed the problem that
videotaping interrogations is an effective solution to the false confession problem. n66 But videotaping as a
"stand-alone" proposal is unlikely to get far. n67 Rather than piling it on top of existing rules, videotaping should be
imposed as a substitute for other restrictions on police--both to make it [*1133] attractive to police and legislators and
to reasonably accommodate society's interests in effective police interrogation. Previously I have explained such a plan
at length, arguing for videotaping of custodial police interrogations coupled with abolition of Miranda's waiver and
questioning cutoff requirements. n68 This proposal has the virtue of both reducing false confessions from the innocent
and increasing truthful confessions from the guilty. Videotaping is the best remedy for the false confession problem
because it allows reconstruction of what happened during interrogation and identification of suspects who have been
induced to spout back information supplied by the police. n69 At the same time, relaxing the Miranda requirements
eliminates very real costs from the decision. n70 The relaxation will not enlarge any false confession problem as
exists. Persons susceptible to false confessions are particularly unlikely to be helped by the Miranda rules because they
trust the police n71 and are very likely to waive their Miranda rights to convince the police of their innocence. n72 If
anyone doubts this point, recall that all of the false confessions cited by Ofshe and Leo occurred under the Miranda
regime.
As Justice Holmes might have put it, the videotaping and scaled-back Miranda proposal has both dramatic and
quantitative appeal--which is what academic suggestions need to actually become real world policy reform. Ofshe, Leo,
and Alschuler should support this balanced idea or, at the very least, explain where they stand on its merits. But instead
they maintain a studious silence on the idea, focusing single-mindedly on their own plans to eliminate such false
confessions may exist. Time will tell whether their proposals will go anywhere, but my sense is that they will languish.
Without much of a nod to competing concerns, the proposals simply will not advance in fora concerned not only about
the treatment of criminal suspects but also about the conviction of guilty criminals. If this prediction is accurate, then
the innocent persons at the heart of the Ofshe-Leo and Alschuler articles will not be helped. The innocent, of course,
would support my more balanced proposal (and others like it) over the status quo. Why won't the academics?
Legal Topics:
For related research and practice materials, see the following legal topics:
Criminal Law & ProcedureInterrogationMiranda RightsPublic Safety ExceptionCriminal Law & ProcedureJuries &
JurorsGeneral OverviewEvidenceRelevanceConfusion, Prejudice & Waste of Time
FOOTNOTES:

n1 Richard Ofshe and Richard A. Leo, The Decision to Confess Falsely: Rational Choice and Irrational
Action, 74 Denv. U. L. Rev. 979 (1997).
n2 Albert W. Alschuler, Constraint and Confession, 74 Denv. U. L. Rev. 957 (1997).
n3 Professors Ofshe and Leo have another paper on this subject that will be published shortly. Richard A.
Leo & Richard Ofshe, The Consequences of False Confessions: Deprivations of Liberty and Miscarriages of
Justice in the Age of Psychological Interrogation, 88 J. Crim. L. & Criminology (forthcoming 1997) (paper
presented at the Annual Meeting of the Law and Society Association, St. Louis, Missouri, May 30, 1997)
[hereinafter Leo & Ofshe, Consequences of False Confessions].

Page 7
74 Denv. U.L. Rev. 1123, *1133

n4 Oliver Wendell Holmes, Law and the Court, in Collected Legal Papers 291, 293 (1920).
n5 384 U.S. 436 (1966).
n6 Alan Wertheimer, Coercion 113 (1987).
n7 Moran v. Burbine, 475 U.S. 412, 433 n.4 (1986).
n8 See Paul G. Cassell & Bret S. Hayman, Police Interrogation in the 1990s: An Empirical Study of the
Effects of Miranda, 43 UCLA L. Rev. 839, 921 (1996).
n9 See 18 U.S.C. § 3501 (1994) (replacing Miranda with voluntariness test); Joseph D. Grano, Confessions,
Truth and the Law (1993) (attacking Miranda as an "illegitimate" decision).
n10 Alan Wertheimer, Punishing the Innocent--Unintentionally, 20 Inquiry 45, 61 (1977).
n11 See, e.g., Paul G. Cassell, All Benefits, No Costs: The Grand Illusion of Miranda's Defenders, 90 Nw.
U L. Rev. 1084, 1121 (1996); Paul G. Cassell, The Costs of the Miranda Mandate: A Lesson in the Dangers of
Inflexible, "Prophylactic" Supreme Court Inventions, 28 Ariz. L. Rev. 299, 311 (1996); Paul G. Cassell &
Richard Fowles, Handcuffing the Cops? A Thirty Year Perspective on Miranda's Effects on Law Enforcement,
50 Stan. L. Rev. (forthcoming 1998); Paul G. Cassell, Miranda's Social Costs: An Empirical Reassessment, 90
Nw. U. L. Rev. 387, 488-89 (1996) [hereinafter Cassell, Social Costs].
n12 See infra notes 66-72 and accompanying text.
n13 Alschuler, supra note 2, at 960-967.
n14 Id. at 974.
n15 Id. at 957 (noting that the article focuses on "constitutional" requirements).
n16 See Alschuler, supra note 2, at 958 n.6 (citing Albert W. Alschuler, A Peculiar Privilege in Historical
Perspective: The Right to Remain Silent, 94 Mich. L. Rev. 2625 (1996)).
n17 Alschuler, supra note 2, at 971.
n18 Id. at 973.
n19 Alschuler also relies on several other alleged consequences of police misrepresentations in support of
his proposal. These appear to be of less importance in his argument and are discussed infra note 57).

Page 8
74 Denv. U.L. Rev. 1123, *1133

n20 Ofshe & Leo, supra note 1, at 983.
n21 Id. ("interrogation manual writers . . . persist in the self-serving and misguided belief that contemporary
psychological methods are not apt to cause an innocent suspect to confess--a fiction that is flatly contradicted by
all of the scientific research on interrogation and confession").
n22 Id. at 984.
n23 Id. at 1117.
n24 Id. at 1119.
n25 Id. at 1120.
n26 See Alschuler, supra note 2, at 969 n.60 (citing Leo & Ofshe, Consequences of False Confessions,
supra note 3); Richard Ofshe & Richard A. Leo, The Social Psychology of Police Interrogation: The Theory and
Classification of True and False Confessions, 16 Studies in Law, Politics & Soc'y 185, 198 (1997) [hereinafter
cited as Ofshe & Leo, Social Psychology of Interrogation]). Alschuler also cites Professor White. Alschuler,
supra, at 26 n.66 (citing Welsh S. White, False Confessions and the Constitution: Safeguards Against Unworthy
Confessions, 32 Harv. C.R.-C.L. L. Rev. 105, 108-09 & nn.26 & 30 (1997)). White, however, concedes that a
determination of the frequency of false confessions "is difficult to make accurately"; White will venture only
(without any further definition of terms) that false confessions are "likely in a small but significant number of
cases." White, supra, at 109, 111. Alschuler also refers to the dubious "study" by Professors Bedau and Radelet.
See Alschuler, supra, at 26 n.66 (citing Hugo Adam Bedau & Michael L. Radelet, Miscarriages of Justice in
Potentially Capital Cases, 40 Stan L. Rev. 21 (1987)). Cf. Stephen J. Markman & Paul G. Cassell, Protecting the
Innocent: A Response to the Bedau-Radelet Study, 41 Stan. L. Rev. 121, 128 (1988) (concluding that article
gives the impression "it is more an argumentative tract than a fair-minded inquiry"). The reference to Bedau and
Radelet seems misplaced, because they most frequently discuss "coerced" false confessions, Bedau & Radelet,
supra, at 57 tbl.6, produced by physical brutality or police perjury, not the psychologically-induced false
confessions that form the basis for the policy recommendations of Alschuler and Ofshe-Leo.
n27 Ofshe & Leo, supra note 1, at 1121.
n28 See, e.g., id. at 983 n.16 (citing Leo & Ofshe, Consequences of False Confessions, supra note 3).
n29 Paul G. Cassell, Protecting the Innocent from False Confessions and Lost Confessions--And From
Miranda, 88 J. Crim. L. & Criminology (forthcoming 1997).
n30 Ofshe & Leo, supra note 1, at 984 n.32 (emphasis added).
n31 Alschuler, supra note 2, at 969 n.60.
n32 Ofshe & Leo, supra note 1, at 1118.

Page 9
74 Denv. U.L. Rev. 1123, *1133

n33 Ofshe & Leo, supra note 1, at 981 n.1.
n34 See, e.g., id. at 1000 n.75 (discussing interrogation of Peter Reilly in 1973).
n35 Each year during the period, police arrested roughly 2.9 million persons for the FBI index crimes of
non-negligent homicide, forcible rape, robbery, aggravated assault, burglary, vehicle theft, and larceny. See, e.g.,
Fed. Bureau of Investigation, U.S. Dep't of Justice, Uniform Crime Reports, Crime in the United States 1995, at
208 tbl.29 (1996) (reporting 1995 arrest totals). About 80% of these arrestees will be interrogated. See Cassell &
Hayman, supra note 8, at 854 (finding 79% of suspects in sample questioned); see also id. (collecting evidence
from other studies that about 80% of all suspects are questioned). This produces a total of about 2.3 million
interrogations per year (2.9 million x 80%), for a ten-year total of 23 million. Looking behind index crimes to all
crimes would produce a total number of interrogations about five times as high. See Fed. Bureau of
Investigation, supra, at 208 tbl.29 (reporting estimated total arrests five times higher than arrests for index
crimes only).
n36 Cf. Paul G. Cassell, The Mysterious Creation of Search and Seizure Exclusionary Rules Under State
Constitutions: The Utah Example, 1993 Utah L. Rev. 751, 833-36 (discussing effect of Utah rules of evidence
on court-created exclusionary rules).
n37 656 F.2d 1147, 1154 (5th Cir. 1981).
n38 Id. at 1149-50.
n39 Id.
n40 See, e.g., 22 C. Wright & K. Graham, Federal Practice and Procedure: Evidence § 5214, at 265-66
(1978 & 1996 Supp.) ("It seems relatively clear that in the weighing process under Rule 403 the judge cannot
consider the credibility of witnesses."); Edward J. Imwinkelried, The Meaning of Probative Value and Prejudice
in Federal Rule of Evidence 403: Can Rule 403 Be Used to Resurrect the Common Law of Evidence, 41 Vand.
L. Rev. 879, 88687 (1988) ("The overwhelming majority of courts asserts that a judge cannot pass on credibility
in assessing probative value.").
n41 Ballou, 656 F.2d at 1150.
n42 Id. at 1154 (internal citations omitted) (first emphasis added).
n43 Id. at 1154.
n44 Ofshe & Leo, supra note 1, at 1118.
n45 See, e.g., id. at 996 (noting acquittal of Richard Bingham after false confession); id. at 1024 (noting
arrest of women who was apparently not tried).

Page 10
74 Denv. U.L. Rev. 1123, *1133

n46 U.S. Const. art. III, § 2.
n47 Alschuler, supra note 2, at 3; see also Colorado v. Connelly, 479 U.S. 157, 167 (1986) ("The aim of the
requirement of due process is not to exclude presumptively false evidence, but to prevent fundamental
unfairness in the use of evidence, whether true or false") (internal quotation omitted).
n48 22 Wright & Miller, supra note 40, at 266.
n49 Imwinkelried, supra note 40, at 887.
n50 Cf. Fred E. Inbau & James P. Manak, Miranda v. Arizona--Is it Worth the Costs? (A Sample Survey,
with Commentary, of the Expenditure of Court Time and Effort), 1 Cal. W.L. Rev. 185 (1988) (discussing
consumption of court time as the result of Miranda issues); Davis v. United States, 512 U.S. 452, 465 (1994)
(Scalia, J., concurring) (same).
n51 Fred E. Inbau et al., Criminal Interrogation and Confessions 84-85 (3d ed. 1986).
n52 Ofshe & Leo, supra note 1, at 1115.
n53 Richard A. Leo, Inside the Interrogation Room: A Qualitative and Quantitative Analysis of
Contemporary American Police Practices, 86 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 266, 279 (1996).
n54 Such a tactic was associated with a confession or admission in 83% of the cases where it was used, a
result that was no a statistically significant improvement over that base success rate of 76%. Id. at 294 tbl.14.
n55 For these groups, confessions resulted at rates of 96% and 88%, respectively. Id. at 295 tbl.15.
n56 Barry Irving, Royal Comm'n on Crim. Proc., Police Interrogation: A Case Study of Current Practice
145 (1980) (Research Study No. 2).
n57 Perhaps recognizing that the prevention of false confession cannot alone justify a ban on police
trickery, Alschuler also justifies his proposal with other intrinsic and empirical consequences from such
representations. Alschuler, supra note 2, at 974. However, it is not clear that these factors add much support for
his proposal. With respect to the intrinsic evil of lying, even the philosopher that Alschuler relies upon most
heavily (Sissela Bok) provides no justification for a ban on misrepresentation. See Christopher Slobogin, Deceit,
Pretext and Trickery: Investigative Lies by Police, 76 Oregon L. Rev. (forthcoming 1997) (analyzing police
deception from a framework "relying principally on the work of noted moral philosopher Sissela Bok" and
concluding that "under Bok's framework . . . a good case can be made for the proposition that post-arrest trickery
[of suspects] is permissible"). With respect to more pragmatic concerns, it is clear that a balancing of interests is
called for. Yet Alschuler, having not discussed at any length the possible harmful consequences from his
proposal, is in a weak position to claim that the balance of advantage tips in its favor. Indeed, Alschuler
concedes in a disarmingly candid sentence that "admittedly, many of the harmful consequences produced by
misrepresenting the strength of the evidence are also produced by deceptive interrogation practices that I do not

Page 11
74 Denv. U.L. Rev. 1123, *1133

disapprove" and "these troublesome consequences are in fact risked by every form of undercover investigation."
Alschuler, supra, at 975 n.88. Alschuler seems to simply leave these pregnant observations hanging.
n58 See Cassell, supra note 29 (developing at length the argument about truthful confessions protecting the
innocent); see also Akhil R. Amar, The Constitutional and Criminal Procedure: First Principles 48 (1997)
(criticizing current doctrine because "courts cripple innocent defendants while the guilty wrap themselves in the
self-incrimination clause and walk free"); Henry J. Friendly, The Fifth Amendment Tomorrow: The Case for
Constitutional Change, 37 U. Cin. L. Rev. 671, 680-81 (1968) (criticizing the Fifth Amendment because "a man
in suspicious circumstances but not in fact guilty is deprived of official interrogation of another whom he knows
to be the true culprit . . . ."); William J. Stuntz, Lawyers, Deceptions, and Evidence Gathering, 79 Va. L. Rev.
1903, 1931 (1993) (concluding "it seems likely that making government investigation easier improves the
welfare of innocent defendants").
n59 See Royal Comm'n on Criminal Justice, Corroboration and Confessions: The Impact of a Rule
Requiring that No Conviction be Sustained on the Basis of Confession Evidence Alone 86 (1993) (deriving this
estimate although cautioning that it might be too high for several reasons).
n60 In fairness to Professor Alschuler, it should be noted that a good part of his article is devoted to
defending the current doctrine that confessions should only be excluded if caused by offensive government
conduct, a proposition leading to greater admissibility of confessions. On balance, however, his proposals would
most likely produce a net reduction in the admissibility of confessions. See supra note 53 and accompanying text
(concluding that 30% of all confessions in America would need to be restructured to comply with Alschuler's
proposals).
n61 See, e.g., Margaret L. Paris, Faults, Fallacies, and the Future of our Criminal Justice System: Trust,
Lies, and Interrogation, 3 Va. J. Soc. Pol'y & L. 3, 44 (1995) (proposing a rule against police lies in interrogation
because, inter alia, "the community will have lost a valuable opportunity to teach the very value that it finds so
objectionably lacking in the suspect"); Slobogin, supra note 57 (proposing restrictions on non-custodial police
interrogations because of lack of judicial determination of appropriateness for interview); White, supra note 26
(proposing restrictions to prevent false confessions); Deborah Young, Unnecessary Evil: Police Lying in
Interrogations, 28 Conn. L. Rev. 425, 477 (1996) (proposing elimination of lying in police interrogations to
allow to help police regain the trust of "the people"); see also Charles J. Ogletree, Are Confessions Really Good
for the Soul? A Proposal to Mirandize Miranda, 100 Harv. L. Rev. 1826, 1842 (1987) (proposing that all
suspects should receive a lawyer before any custodial questioning is allowed, a proposal that would effectively
end most custodial police interrogation). For refreshing exceptions to the rule, see Amar, supra note 58; Grano,
supra note 9.
n62 Modern day academics, indeed, seem to invariably conflate the two. See Grano, supra note 9, at i.
n63 Even here, the academics' analysis is decidedly incomplete. See Cassell, supra note 29.
n64 Gerald M. Caplan, Questioning Miranda, 38 Vand. L. Rev. 1417, 1426 n.47 (1985).
n65 See, e.g., 18 U.S.C. § 3501 (1994) (overruling Miranda and substituting pre-Miranda voluntariness
test); Davis v. United States, 512 U.S. 452, 465 (1994) (Scalia, J., concurring) (concluding that § 3501 "is a

Page 12
74 Denv. U.L. Rev. 1123, *1133

provision of law . . . . reflecting the people's assessment of the proper balance to be struck between concern for
persons interrogated in custody and the needs of effective law enforcement"); see also Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. §
13-3988 (1978) (adopting statute modeled on § 3501).
n66 See, e.g., Cassell, Social Costs, supra note 11, at 488-89 (recommending videotaping to prevent false
confessions); Ofshe & Leo, supra note 1, at 1118; Alschuler, supra note 2, at 977; White, supra note 26, at
153-54.
n67 See Alschuler, supra note 2, at 977 (concluding "most police departments resist" videotaping); Cassell,
supra note 38.
n68 See Cassell, Social Costs, supra note 11, at 486-98.
n69 See id. at 488-89; see also Ofshe & Leo, supra note 1, at 1118; Alschuler, supra note 2, at 977.
n70 See Cassell, Social Costs, supra note 11, at 492-97.
n71 See Gisli H. Gudjonson, The Psychology of Interrogations, Confessions and Testimony 232 (1992)
(noting common personality factor of false confessors of "good trust of people in authority").
n72 See, e.g., id. at 226 (discussing case of Peter Reilly, who did not exercise his Miranda right to a lawyer
because "I hadn't done anything wrong"); Roger Parloff, 1993: False Confessions, Am. Law., Dec. 1994, at 33,
34 (reporting that suspect who would later give false confession waived rights because "I had nothing to hide").
See generally, Corey J. Ayling, Comment, Corroborating Confessions: An Empirical Analysis of Legal
Safeguards Against False Confessions, 1984 Wis. L. Rev. 1121, 1194-98 (arguing that Miranda rules have
limited utility in preventing false confessions).

 

 

Disciplinary Self-Help Litigation Manual - Side
CLN Subscribe Now Ad
The Habeas Citebook Ineffective Counsel Side